Thus, although the court in Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. 60, identified three factors--advertising format, product references, and commercial motivation--that in combination supported a characterization of commercial speech in that case, the court not only rejected the notion that any of these factors is sufficient by itself, but it also declined to hold that all of these factors in combination, or any one of them individually, is necessary to support a commercial speech characterization. The high court also cautioned, as it had in past cases, that statements may properly be categorized as commercial "notwithstanding the fact that they contain discussions of important public issues," and that "advertising which 'links a product to a current public debate' is not thereby entitled to the constitutional protection afforded noncommercial speech," explaining further that "[a]dvertisers should not be permitted to immunize false or misleading product information from government regulation simply by including references to public issues." We conclude, therefore, that when a court must decide whether particular speech may be subjected to laws aimed at preventing false advertising or other forms of commercial deception, categorizing a particular statement as commercial or noncommercial speech requires consideration of three elements: the speaker, the intended audience, and the content of the message. Here, the first element--a commercial speaker--is satisfied because the speakers--Nike and its officers and directors--are engaged in commerce. Specifically, they manufacture, import, distribute, and sell consumer goods in the form of athletic shoes and apparel.
The third element--representations of fact of a commercial nature--is also present. In describing its own labor policies, and the practices and working conditions in factories where its products are made, Nike was making factual representations about its own business operations. In speaking to consumers about working conditions and labor practices in the factories where its products are made, Nike addressed matters within its own knowledge. The wages paid to the factories' employees, the hours they work, the way they are treated, and whether the environmental conditions under which they work violate local health and safety laws, are all matters likely to be within the personal knowledge of Nike executives, employees, or subcontractors. Thus, Nike was in a position to readily verify the truth of any factual assertions it made on these topics. |
Kasky v. Nike, Inc. (2002)27 Cal.4th 939 , 119 Cal.Rptr.2d 296; 45
P.3d 243[No. S087859. May 2, 2002.]
[As modified May 22, 2002.]
KENNARD, J.-
Acting on behalf of the public, plaintiff brought this action seeking
monetary and injunctive relief under California laws designed to curb
false advertising and unfair competition. Plaintiff alleged that defendant
corporation, in response to public criticism, and to induce consumers
to continue to buy its products, made false statements of fact about
its labor practices and about working conditions in factories that
make its products. Applying established principles of appellate review,
we must assume in this opinion that these allegations are true. [27
Cal.4th 946]
The issue here is whether defendant corporation's false statements
are commercial or noncommercial speech for purposes of constitutional
free speech analysis under the state and federal Constitutions. Resolution
of this issue is important because commercial speech receives a lesser
degree of constitutional protection than many other forms of expression,
and because governments may entirely prohibit commercial speech that
is false or misleading.
Because the messages in question were directed by a commercial speaker
to a commercial audience, and because they made representations of
fact about the speaker's own business operations for the purpose of
promoting sales of its products, we conclude that these messages are
commercial speech for purposes of applying state laws barring false
and misleading commercial messages. Because the Court of Appeal concluded
otherwise, we will reverse its judgment.
Our holding, based on decisions of the United States Supreme Court,
in no way prohibits any business enterprise from speaking out on issues
of public importance or from vigorously defending its own labor practices.
It means only that when a business enterprise, to promote and defend
its sales and profits, makes factual representations about its own
products or its own operations, it must speak truthfully. Unlike our
dissenting colleagues, we do not consider this a remarkable or intolerable
burden to impose on the business community. We emphasize that this
lawsuit is still at a preliminary stage, and that whether any false
representations were made is a disputed issue that has yet to be resolved.
I. FACTS
This case comes before us after the superior court sustained defendants'
demurrers to plaintiff's first amended complaint. We therefore begin
by summarizing that complaint's allegations, accepting the truth of
the allegations, as we must, for the limited purposes of reviewing
the superior court's ruling. (See Stevenson v. Superior Court (1997)
16 Cal.4th 880, 885; accord, Charles J. Vacanti, M.D., Inc. v. State
Comp. Ins. Fund (2001) 24 Cal.4th 800, 807; Santa Monica Beach, Ltd.
v. Superior Court (1999) 19 Cal.4th 952, 957.)
A. Allegations of the First Amended Complaint
Plaintiff Marc Kasky is a California resident suing on behalf of the
general public of the State of California under Business and Professions
[27 Cal.4th 947] Code sections 17204 and 17535. fn. 1 Defendant Nike,
Inc. (Nike) is an Oregon corporation with its principal place of business
in that state; Nike is authorized to do business in California and
does promote, distribute, and sell its products in this state. The
individual defendants (Philip Knight, Thomas Clarke, Mark Parker, Stephen
Gomez, and David Taylor) are officers and/or directors of Nike.
Nike manufactures and sells athletic shoes and apparel. In 1997, it
reported annual revenues of $9.2 billion, with annual expenditures
for advertising and marketing of almost $1 billion. Most of Nike's
products are manufactured by subcontractors in China, Vietnam, and
Indonesia. Most of the workers who make Nike products are women under
the age of 24. Since March 1993, under a memorandum of understanding
with its subcontractors, Nike has assumed responsibility for its subcontractors'
compliance with applicable local laws and regulations concerning minimum
wage, overtime, occupational health and safety, and environmental protection.
Beginning at least in October 1996 with a report on the television
news program 48 Hours, and continuing at least through November and
December of 1997 with the publication of articles in the Financial
Times, the New York Times, the San Francisco Chronicle, the Buffalo
News, the Oregonian, the Kansas City Star, and the Sporting News, various
persons and organizations alleged that in the factories where Nike
products are made workers were paid less than the applicable local
minimum wage; required to work overtime; allowed and encouraged to
work more overtime hours than applicable local law allowed; subjected
to physical, verbal, and sexual abuse; and exposed to toxic chemicals,
noise, heat, and dust without adequate safety equipment, in violation
of applicable local occupational health and safety regulations.
In response to this adverse publicity, and for the purpose of maintaining
and increasing its sales and profits, Nike and the individual defendants
made statements to the California consuming public that plaintiff
alleges were false and misleading. Specifically, Nike and the individual
defendants
said that workers who make Nike products are protected from physical
and sexual abuse, that they are paid in accordance with applicable
local laws and regulations governing wages and hours, that they are
paid on average double the applicable local minimum wage, that they
receive a "living wage," that they receive free meals and
health care, and that their working conditions are in compliance
with applicable local laws and regulations governing occupational
health
and safety. Nike and the individual defendants made these [27 Cal.4th
948] statements in press releases, in letters to newspapers, in a
letter to university presidents and athletic directors, and in other
documents
distributed for public relations purposes. Nike also bought full-page
advertisements in leading newspapers to publicize a report that GoodWorks
International, LLC., had prepared under a contract with Nike. The
report was based on an investigation by former United States Ambassador
Andrew
Young, and it found no evidence of illegal or unsafe working conditions
at Nike factories in China, Vietnam, and Indonesia.
Plaintiff alleges that Nike and the individual defendants made these
false and misleading statements because of their negligence and carelessness
and "with knowledge or reckless disregard of the laws of California
prohibiting false and misleading statements."
B. Superior Court Proceedings
Based on these factual allegations, plaintiff's first amended complaint
sought relief in the form of restitution requiring Nike to "disgorge
all monies . . . acquired by means of any act found . . . to be an
unlawful and/or unfair business practice," and relief in the form
of an injunction requiring Nike to "undertake a Court-approved
public information campaign" to correct any false or misleading
statement, and to cease misrepresenting the working conditions under
which Nike products are made. Plaintiff also sought reasonable attorney
fees and costs and other relief that the court deemed just and proper.
Nike demurred to the first amended complaint on grounds, among others,
that it failed to state facts sufficient to constitute a cause of
action against Nike and that the relief plaintiff was seeking "is absolutely
barred by the First Amendment to the United States Constitution and
Article I, section 2(a) of the California Constitution." The
individual defendants separately demurred to the first amended complaint
on the
same grounds.
On January 7, 1999, the superior court held a hearing on defendants'
demurrers. At the hearing, the court stated that it considered the
crucial question to be whether Nike's allegedly false and misleading
statements noted in the first amended complaint constituted commercial
or noncommercial speech, because the answer to this question would
determine the amount of protection the statements would receive under
the federal and state constitutional free speech guarantees. After
considering the arguments and authorities submitted by the parties,
the court took the matter under submission and later sustained the
demurrers without leave to amend. Plaintiff appealed from the judgment
dismissing the complaint. [27 Cal.4th 949]
C. Court of Appeal Proceedings
The Court of Appeal affirmed the judgment. Like the superior
court, the appellate court identified as the crucial issue whether
Nike's
allegedly false and misleading statements were commercial or noncommercial
speech for purposes of analyzing the protections afforded by the First
Amendment to the federal Constitution and by article I, section 2 of
the California Constitution. Also like the superior court, the appellate
court concluded that Nike's statements were noncommercial speech and
therefore subject to the greatest measure of protection under the constitutional
free speech provisions. The court stated that this determination "compels
the conclusion that the trial court properly sustained the defendants'
demurrer without leave to amend." We granted plaintiff's petition
for review.
II. CALIFORNIA LAWS PROHIBITING CONSUMER DECEPTION
A. The Unfair Competition Law
[1] California's unfair competition law (UCL) (§ 17200 et seq.)
defines "unfair competition" to mean and include "any
unlawful, unfair or fraudulent business act or practice and unfair,
deceptive, untrue or misleading advertising and any act prohibited
by [the false advertising law (§ 17500 et seq.)]." (§ 17200.)
The UCL's purpose is to protect both consumers and competitors
by promoting fair competition in commercial markets for goods and
services.
(Barquis
v. Merchants Collection Assn. (1972) 7 Cal.3d 94, 110.)
The UCL's scope is broad. By defining unfair competition to include
any "unlawful . . . business act or practice" (§ 17200,
italics added), the UCL permits violations of other laws to be treated
as unfair competition that is independently actionable. (Cel-Tech Communications,
Inc. v. Los Angeles Cellular Telephone Co. (1999) 20 Cal.4th 163, 180.)
Here, for instance, plaintiff's first amended complaint alleged that
Nike and the individual defendants violated the UCL by committing actual
fraud as defined in and prohibited by Civil Code section 1572 and deceit
as defined in and prohibited by Civil Code sections 1709 and 1710.
By defining unfair competition to include also any "unfair or
fraudulent business act or practice" (§ 17200, italics
added), the UCL sweeps within its scope acts and practices not
specifically proscribed by any other law. (Cel-Tech Communications,
Inc. v. Los
Angeles Cellular Telephone Co., supra, at p. 180.) Plaintiff's
first amended complaint also alleged a UCL violation of this type.
[2] Not only public prosecutors, but also "any person acting for
the interests of . . . the general public," may bring an action
for relief under the [27 Cal.4th 950] UCL. (§ 17204.) Under this
provision, a private plaintiff may bring a UCL action even when "the
conduct alleged to constitute unfair competition violates a statute
for the direct enforcement of which there is no private right of action." (Stop
Youth Addiction, Inc. v. Lucky Stores, Inc. (1998) 17 Cal.4th 553,
565.) "This court has repeatedly recognized the importance of
these private enforcement efforts." (Kraus v. Trinity Management
Services (2000) 23 Cal.4th 116, 126.)
In a suit under the UCL, a public prosecutor may collect civil
penalties, but a private plaintiff's remedies are "generally limited to injunctive
relief and restitution." (Cel-Tech Communications, Inc. v. Los
Angeles Cellular Telephone Co., supra, 20 Cal.4th at p. 179; see §§ 17203,
17206; ABC Internat. Traders, Inc. v. Matsushita Electric Corp.
(1997) 14 Cal.4th 1247, 1268.) An order for restitution is one
'compelling
a UCL defendant to return money obtained through an unfair business
practice to those persons in interest from whom the property was
taken.' (Kraus v. Trinity Management Services, Inc., supra, 23
Cal.4th at pp.
126-127.)
B. The False Advertising Law
[3] California's false advertising law (§ 17500 et seq.) makes
it "unlawful for any person, . . . corporation . . ., or any employee
thereof with intent directly or indirectly to dispose of real or personal
property or to perform services . . . or to induce the public to enter
into any obligation relating thereto, to make or disseminate . . .
before the public in this state, . . . in any newspaper or other publication
. . . or in any other manner or means whatever . . . any statement,
concerning that real or personal property or those services . . . which
is untrue or misleading, and which is known, or which by the exercise
of reasonable care should be known, to be untrue or misleading . .
. ." (§ 17500.) Violation of this provision is a misdemeanor.
(Ibid.) As with the UCL, an action for violation of the false advertising
law may be brought either by a public prosecutor or by "any person
acting for the interests of itself, its members or the general public," and
the remedies available to a successful private plaintiff include restitution
and injunctive relief. (§ 17535.)
C. Common Features of the UCL and the False Advertising Law
[4] This court has recognized that "[a]ny violation of the false
advertising law . . . necessarily violates" the UCL. (Committee
on Children's Television, Inc. v. General Foods Corp. (1983) 35 Cal.3d
197, [27 Cal.4th 951] 210.) We have also recognized that these laws
prohibit "not only advertising which is false, but also advertising
which[,] although true, is either actually misleading or which has
a capacity, likelihood or tendency to deceive or confuse the public." (Leoni
v. State Bar (1985) 39 Cal.3d 609, 626.) Thus, to state a claim under
either the UCL or the false advertising law, based on false advertising
or promotional practices, "it is necessary only to show that 'members
of the public are likely to be deceived.' " (Committee
on Children's Television, Inc. v. General Foods Corp., supra,
35
Cal.3d at p. 211;
accord, Bank of the West v. Superior Court (1992) 2 Cal.4th
1254, 1267.)
III. CONSTITUTIONAL PROTECTIONS FOR SPEECH
A. Federal Constitution
1. Constitutional text and its application to state laws
The United States Constitution's First Amendment, part of the Bill
of Rights, provides in part that "Congress shall make no law .
. . abridging the freedom of speech . . . ." (U.S. Const.,
1st Amend.) [5] Although by its terms this provision limits
only Congress,
the United States Supreme Court has held that the Fourteenth
Amendment's due process clause makes the freedom of speech
provision operate
to limit the authority of state and local governments as
well. (McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm'n (1995) 514 U.S.
334, 336,
fn. 1.)
2. Constitutional protection of commercial speech
Although advertising has played an important role in our nation's
culture since its early days, and although state regulation
of commercial advertising
and commercial transactions also has a long history, it was
not until the 1970's that the United States Supreme Court extended
First Amendment
protection to commercial messages. In 1975, the court declared
that it was error to assume "that advertising, as such, was entitled
to no First Amendment protection." (Bigelow v. Virginia (1975)
421 U.S. 809, 825.) The next year, the court held that a state's complete
ban on advertising prescription drug prices violated the First Amendment.
(Va. Pharmacy Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council (1976) 425 U.S. 748, 770.)
The high court observed that "the free flow of commercial information
is indispensable" not only "to the proper allocation of resources
in a free enterprise system" but also "to the formation of
intelligent opinions as to how that system ought to be regulated or
altered." (Id. at p. 765.) [27 Cal.4th 952]
3. Tests for commercial and noncommercial speech regulations
[6] "[T]he [federal] Constitution accords less protection to commercial
speech than to other constitutionally safeguarded forms of expression." (Bolger
v. Youngs Drug Products Corp. (1983) 463 U.S. 60, 64-65 (Bolger).)
For noncommercial speech entitled to full First Amendment protection,
a content-based regulation is valid under the First Amendment only
if it can withstand strict scrutiny, which requires that the regulation
be narrowly tailored (that is, the least restrictive means) to promote
a compelling government interest. (United States v. Playboy Entertainment
Group, Inc. (2000) 529 U.S. 803, 813; Consolidated Edison Co. v. Public
Serv. Comm'n (1980) 447 U.S. 530, 540.)
"
By contrast, regulation of commercial speech based on content is less
problematic." (Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. at p. 65.) To determine
the validity of a content-based regulation of commercial speech, the
United States Supreme Court has articulated an intermediate-scrutiny
test. The court first articulated this test in Central Hudson Gas & Elec.
v. Public Serv. Comm'n (1980) 447 U.S. 557 (Central Hudson) and has
since referred to it as the Central Hudson test. The court explained
the components of the test this way: "At the outset, we must determine
whether the expression is protected by the First Amendment. For commercial
speech to come within that provision, it at least must concern lawful
activity and not be misleading. Next, we ask whether the asserted governmental
interest is substantial. If both inquiries yield positive answers,
we must determine whether the regulation directly advances the governmental
interest asserted, and whether it is not more extensive than is necessary
to serve that interest." (Id. at p. 566, italics added; accord,
Lorillard Tobacco Co. v. Reilly (2001) 533 U.S. 525, __ [121 S.Ct.
2404, 2421]; Greater New Orleans Broadcasting Assn., Inc. v. United
States (1999) 527 U.S. 173, 183.) The court has clarified that the
last part of the test--determining whether the regulation is not more
extensive than "necessary"--does not require the government
to adopt the least restrictive means, but instead requires only a "reasonable
fit" between the government's purpose and the means
chosen to achieve it. (Board of Trustees, State Univ. of
N.Y. v. Fox
(1989) 492 U.S. 469, 480.) [27 Cal.4th 953]
4. Regulation of false or misleading speech
[7] "[T]here is no constitutional value in false statements of
fact. Neither the intentional lie nor the careless error materially
advances society's interest in 'uninhibited, robust, and wide-open
debate on public issues.' " (Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. (1974)
418 U.S. 323, 340.) For this reason, "[u]ntruthful speech, commercial
or otherwise, has never been protected for its own sake." (Va.
Pharmacy Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council, supra, 425 U.S. at
p. 771.)
Nevertheless, in some instances the First Amendment imposes
restraints on lawsuits seeking damages for injurious falsehoods.
It does
so "to
eliminate the risk of undue self-censorship and the suppression of
truthful material" (Herbert v. Lando (1979) 441 U.S. 153, 172)
and thereby to give freedom of expression the " 'breathing space' " it
needs to survive (New York Times Co. v. Sullivan (1964) 376 U.S. 254,
272; Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of U.S., Inc. (1984) 466 U.S. 485,
513). Thus, "some false and misleading statements are entitled
to First Amendment protection in the political realm." (Rubin
v. Coors Brewing Co. (1995) 514 U.S. 476, 495 (conc. opn.
of Stevens, J.).)
[8] But the United States Supreme Court has explained that
the First Amendment's protection for false statements is
not universal.
(See
Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders (1985) 472 U.S. 749,
762 (plur. opn. of Powell, J.) [stating that when speech "concerns
no public issue" and is "wholly false and clearly damaging," it "warrants
no special protection" under the First Amendment].) In particular,
commercial speech that is false or misleading is not entitled to First
Amendment protection and "may be prohibited entirely." (In
re R.M.J. (1982) 455 U.S. 191, 203; see also Edenfield v. Fane (1993)
507 U.S. 761, 768 [observing that "the State may ban commercial
expression that is fraudulent or deceptive without further justification"];
Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. at p. 69 [observing that "[t]he State
may deal effectively with false, deceptive, or misleading sales techniques"];
Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary Counsel (1985) 471 U.S. 626, 638
[observing that "[t]he States and the Federal Government are free
to prevent the dissemination of commercial speech that is false, deceptive,
or misleading"]; Central Hudson, supra, 447 U.S. at p. 566 [stating
that for commercial speech to come within First Amendment protection "it
. . . must . . . not be misleading"]; [27 Cal.4th 954] Bates v.
State Bar of Arizona (1977) 433 U.S. 350, 383 [stating that "the
leeway for untruthful or misleading expression that has been allowed
in other contexts has little force in the commercial arena"].)
With regard to misleading commercial speech, the United States
Supreme Court has drawn a distinction between, on the one
hand, speech that
is actually or inherently misleading, and, on the other hand,
speech that is only potentially misleading. Actually or inherently
misleading
commercial speech is treated the same as false commercial
speech, which the state may prohibit entirely. (In re R.M.J.,
supra,
455 U.S. at
p. 203; Ibanez v. Florida Dept. of Business & Professional Regulation,
Bd. of Accountancy (1994) 512 U.S. 136, 150.) By comparison, "[s]tates
may not completely ban potentially misleading speech if narrower limitations
can ensure that the information is presented in a nonmisleading manner." (Ibanez
v. Florida Dept. of Business & Professional Regulation, Bd. of
Accountancy, supra, at p. 152; see also Peel v. Attorney Reg. & Disciplinary
Comm'n (1990) 496 U.S. 91, 100; In re R.M.J., supra, at p.
203.)
As one Supreme Court Justice has remarked, "the elimination of
false and deceptive claims serves to promote the one facet of commercial
price and product advertising that warrants First Amendment protection--its
contribution to the flow of accurate and reliable information relevant
to public and private decisionmaking." (Va. Pharmacy Bd. v. Va.
Consumer Council, supra, 425 U.S. at p. 781 (conc. opn. of Stewart,
J.); see also 44 Liquormart, Inc. v. Rhode Island (1996) 517 U.S. 484,
496, 501 (plur. opn. of Stevens, J.).) Thus, the high court has acknowledged
that state laws may require a commercial message to "appear in
such a form, or include such additional information, warnings, and
disclaimers, as are necessary to prevent its being deceptive." (Va.
Pharmacy Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council, supra, 425 U.S. at p. 772, fn.
24.) In the court's words, "[t]he First Amendment . . . does not
prohibit the State from insuring that the stream of commercial information
flow[s] cleanly as well as freely." (Id. at pp. 771-772.)
5. Reasons for the distinction
[9] The United States Supreme Court has given three reasons for the
distinction between commercial and noncommercial speech in general
and, more particularly, for withholding First Amendment protection
from commercial speech that is false or actually or inherently misleading.
[27 Cal.4th 955]
First, "[t]he truth of commercial speech . . . may be more easily
verifiable by its disseminator than . . . news reporting or political
commentary, in that ordinarily the advertiser seeks to disseminate
information about a specific product or service that he himself provides
and presumably knows more about than anyone else." (Va. Pharmacy
Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council, supra, 425 U.S. at p. 772, fn. 24, italics
added; see also id. at p. 777 (conc. opn. of Stewart, J.) [stating
that "[t]he advertiser's access to the truth about his product
and its price substantially eliminates any danger that governmental
regulation of false or misleading price or product advertising will
chill accurate and nondeceptive commercial expression"]; accord,
44 Liquormart, Inc. v. Rhode Island, supra, 517 U.S. at p. 499 (plur.
opn. of Stevens, J.); Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss
Builders, supra, 472 U.S. at p. 758, fn. 5 (plur. opn. of
Powell, J.); Bose
Corp. v. Consumers Union of U.S., Inc., supra, 466 U.S. at
p. 504, fn. 22.)
Second, commercial speech is hardier than noncommercial speech
in the sense that commercial speakers, because they act from
a profit
motive,
are less likely to experience a chilling effect from speech
regulation. (Va. Pharmacy Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council, supra,
425 U.S. at
p. 772, fn. 24 [stating that "since advertising is the Sine qua non of
commercial profits, there is little likelihood of its being chilled
by proper regulation and forgone entirely"]; accord, 44 Liquormart,
Inc. v. Rhode Island, supra, 517 U.S. at p. 499 (plur. opn. of Stevens,
J.); Board of Trustees, State Univ. of N.Y. v. Fox, supra, 492 U.S.
at p. 481; Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders,
supra, 472 U.S. at p. 758, fn. 5 (plur. opn. of Powell, J.).)
Third, governmental authority to regulate commercial transactions
to prevent commercial harms justifies a power to regulate
speech that
is " 'linked inextricably' to those transactions." (44 Liquormart,
Inc. v. Rhode Island, supra, 517 U.S. at p. 499 (plur. opn. of Stevens,
J.); Edenfield v. Fane, supra, 507 U.S. at p. 767; Friedman v. Rogers
(1979) 440 U.S. 1, 10, fn. 9.) The high court has identified "preventing
commercial harms" as "the typical reason why commercial speech
can be subject to greater governmental regulation than noncommercial
speech" (Cincinnati v. Discovery Network, Inc. (1993) 507 U.S.
410, 426), and it has explained that "[t]he interest in preventing
commercial harms justifies more intensive regulation of commercial
speech than noncommercial speech even when they are intermingled in
the same publications" (id. at p. 426, fn. 21). (See also [27
Cal.4th 956] Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co., supra, 514 U.S. at p. 496
(conc. opn. of Stevens, J.) [stating that "[t]he evils of false
commercial speech, which may have an immediate harmful impact on commercial
transactions, together with the ability of purveyors of commercial
speech to control falsehoods, explains why we tolerate more governmental
regulation of this speech than of most other speech"].)
6. Distinguishing commercial from noncommercial speech
[10] The United States Supreme Court has stated that the category
of commercial speech consists at its core of " 'speech proposing
a commercial transaction.' " (Central Hudson, supra, 447 U.S.
at p. 562; Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. at p. 66.) Although in one case
the court said that this description was "the test for identifying
commercial speech" (Board of Trustees, State Univ. of N.Y. v.
Fox, supra, 492 U.S. at pp. 473-474), in other decisions the court
has indicated that the category of commercial speech is not limited
to this core segment. For example, the court has accepted as commercial
speech a statement of alcohol content on the label of a beer bottle
(Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co., supra, 514 U.S. at pp. 481-482), as well
as statements on an attorney's letterhead and business cards identifying
the attorney as a CPA (certified public accountant) and CFP (certified
financial planner) (Ibanez v. Florida Dept. of Business & Professional
Regulation, Bd. of Accountancy, supra, 512 U.S. at p. 142).
Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. 60, presented the United States
Supreme Court with the question whether a federal law prohibiting
the mailing of
unsolicited advertisements for contraceptives violated
the
federal Constitution's free speech provision as applied
to certain mailings
by a corporation that manufactured, sold, and distributed
contraceptives. One category of mailings consisted of "informational pamphlets
discussing the desirability and availability of prophylactics in general
or [the corporation's] products in particular." (Id. at p. 62,
fn. omitted.) The court noted that these pamphlets did not merely propose
commercial transactions. (Id. at p. 66.) Although the pamphlets were
conceded to be advertisements, that fact alone did not make them commercial
speech because paid advertisements are sometimes used to convey political
or other messages unconnected to a product or service or commercial
transaction. (Ibid., citing New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, supra,
376 U.S. at pp. 265-266.) The court also found that references to specific
products and the economic motivation of the speaker were each, considered
in isolation, insufficient to make the pamphlets commercial speech.
[27 Cal.4th 957] (Bolger, supra, at pp. 66-67.) The court concluded,
however, that the combination of these three factors--advertising format,
product references, and commercial motivation--provided "strong
support" for characterizing the pamphlets as commercial
speech. (Id. at p. 67.)
In two important footnotes, the high court provided additional
insight into the distinction between commercial and noncommercial
speech.
In one footnote, the court gave this caution: "[We do not] mean to
suggest that each of the characteristics present in this case must
necessarily be present in order for speech to be commercial. For example,
we express no opinion as to whether reference to any particular product
or service is a necessary element of commercial speech." (Bolger,
supra, 463 U.S. at p. 67, fn. 14.)
In the other footnote, after observing that one of the
pamphlets at issue discussed condoms in general without
referring specifically
to
the corporation's own products, the court said: "That a product
is referred to generically does not, however, remove it from the realm
of commercial speech. For example, a company with sufficient control
of the market for a product may be able to promote the product without
reference to its own brand names. Or a trade association may make statements
about a product without reference to specific brand names." (Bolger,
supra, 463 U.S. at p. 66, fn. 13.)
Thus, although the court in Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. 60, identified
three factors--advertising format, product references, and commercial
motivation--that in combination supported a characterization of commercial
speech in that case, the court not only rejected the notion that any
of these factors is sufficient by itself, but it also declined to hold
that all of these factors in combination, or any one of them individually,
is necessary to support a commercial speech characterization.
The high court also cautioned, as it had in past
cases, that statements may properly be categorized as
commercial "notwithstanding the
fact that they contain discussions of important public issues," and
that "advertising which 'links a product to a current public debate'
is not thereby entitled to the constitutional protection afforded noncommercial
speech," explaining further that "[a]dvertisers should not
be permitted to immunize false or misleading product information from
government regulation simply by including references to public issues." (Bolger,
supra, 463 U.S. at pp. 67-68, fn. omitted; accord, Board of Trustees,
State Univ. of N.Y. v. Fox, supra, 492 U.S. 469, 475; [27 Cal.4th 958]
Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary Counsel, supra, 471 U.S. at p. 637,
fn. 7; see also Greater New Orleans Broadcasting v. U.S., supra, 527
U.S. at p. 184 [recognizing that commercial speech may concern a "subject
of intense public debate"].)
Since its decision in Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. 60, the
United States Supreme Court has acknowledged that "ambiguities may exist at
the margins of the category of commercial speech." (Edenfield
v. Fane, supra, 507 U.S. at p. 765; see also Cincinnati v. Discovery
Network, Inc., supra, 507 U.S. at p. 419 [recognizing "the difficulty
of drawing bright lines that will clearly cabin commercial speech in
a distinct category"]; Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary Counsel,
supra, 471 U.S. at p. 637 [stating that "the precise bounds of
the category of . . . commercial speech" are "subject to
doubt, perhaps"].) Justice Stevens in particular has remarked
that "the borders of the commercial speech category are not nearly
as clear as the Court has assumed" (Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co.,
supra, 514 U.S. at p. 493 (conc. opn. of Stevens, J.)), and he has
suggested that the distinction cannot rest solely on the form or content
of the statement, or the motive of the speaker, but instead must rest
on the relationship between the speech at issue and the justification
for distinguishing commercial from noncommercial speech. In his words, "any
description of commercial speech that is intended to identify the category
of speech entitled to less First Amendment protection should relate
to the reasons for permitting broader regulation: namely, commercial
speech's potential to mislead." (Id. at p. 494 (conc.
opn. of Stevens, J.).)
B. The State Constitution
1. Constitutional text
The California Constitution's article I, entitled the Declaration
of Rights, guarantees freedom of speech in subdivision
(a) of section 2. It provides: "Every person may freely speak, write and publish
his or her sentiments on all subjects, being responsible for the abuse
of that right. A law may not restrain or abridge liberty of speech
or press." (Cal. Const., art. I, § 2, subd.
(a).)
2. Scope of the state constitutional provision
[11] The state Constitution's free speech provision is "at least
as broad" as (Gerawan Farming, Inc. v. Lyons (2000)
24 Cal.4th 468, 490) and in some ways is broader than
(id. at
[27 Cal.4th
959] p. 491; Blatty v. New York Times Co. (1986) 42 Cal.3d
1033, 1041)
the comparable provision of the federal Constitution's
First Amendment.
3. Commercial speech protection under the state Constitution
[12] The state Constitution's free speech provision, which provides
that "[e]very person may freely speak . . . on all subjects" (Cal.
Const., art. I, § 2, subd. (a), italics added), protects commercial
speech, at least when such speech is "in the form of truthful
and nonmisleading messages about lawful products and services." (Gerawan
Farming, Inc. v. Lyons, supra, 24 Cal.4th at p. 493.) This court has
indicated, however, that our state Constitution does not prohibit the
imposition of sanctions for misleading commercial advertisements. (In
re Morse (1995) 11 Cal.4th 184, 200, fn. 4.) Allowing such sanctions
is consistent with the text of the state constitutional provision,
which makes anyone who "abuse[s]" the right of freedom of
speech "responsible" for the misconduct. (Cal. Const., art.
I, § 2, subd. (a); see Brown v. Kelly Broadcasting
Co. (1989) 48 Cal.3d 711, 746.) Our Courts of Appeal
have held
that neither
the UCL nor the false advertising law on its face violates
the state Constitution's
free speech provision as an impermissible regulation
of commercial speech. (People v. Superior Court (Olson)
(1979)
96 Cal.App.3d
181, 195, cert. den. (1980) 446 U.S. 935; accord, Keimer
v. Buena Vista
Books, Inc. (1999) 75 Cal.App.4th 1220, 1230, fn. 10.)
This court has never suggested that the state and federal Constitutions
impose different boundaries between the categories of commercial and
noncommercial speech. In our most recent decision on this point, Leoni
v. State Bar, supra, 39 Cal.3d 609 (Leoni), this court addressed whether
an attorney's solicitation of clients by means of allegedly misleading
mass mailings and information was protected by the free speech provisions
of the United States and California Constitutions. We used the same
analysis for both constitutional provisions. (Id. at p. 614, fn. 2.)
To determine whether the attorney's mailings were commercial or noncommercial
speech, we relied on the three factors that the United States Supreme
Court had used in Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. 60: advertising format, product
references, and economic motivation. After concluding that two of these
factors were present (because the mailings referred specifically to
the attorney's services and the attorney had an economic motivation
in sending them), we concluded that the presence of these two factors
was sufficient to make the mailings commercial speech for purposes
of the free speech protections of both the federal and the state Constitutions.
(Leoni, supra, at pp. 623-624.) [27 Cal.4th 960]
IV. ANALYSIS
A. The United States Constitution
[13] The United States Supreme Court has not adopted an all-purpose
test to distinguish commercial from noncommercial speech under the
First Amendment, nor has this court adopted such a test under the state
Constitution, nor do we propose to do so here. A close reading of the
high court's commercial speech decisions suggests, however, that it
is possible to formulate a limited-purpose test. We conclude, therefore,
that when a court must decide whether particular speech may be subjected
to laws aimed at preventing false advertising or other forms of commercial
deception, categorizing a particular statement as commercial or noncommercial
speech requires consideration of three elements: the speaker, the intended
audience, and the content of the message.
In typical commercial speech cases, the speaker is likely to be someone
engaged in commerce--that is, generally, the production, distribution,
or sale of goods or services--or someone acting on behalf of a person
so engaged, and the intended audience is likely to be actual or potential
buyers or customers of the speaker's goods or services, or persons
acting for actual or potential buyers or customers, or persons (such
as reporters or reviewers) likely to repeat the message to or otherwise
influence actual or potential buyers or customers. Considering the
identity of both the speaker and the target audience is consistent
with, and implicit in, the United States Supreme Court's commercial
speech decisions, each of which concerned a speaker engaged in the
sale or hire of products or services conveying a message to a person
or persons likely to want, and be willing to pay for, that product
or service. The high court has frequently spoken of commercial speech
as speech proposing a commercial transaction (e.g., Central Hudson,
supra, 447 U.S. at p. 562), thus implying that commercial speech typically
is communication between persons who engage in such transactions.
In Bolger, moreover, the court stated that in deciding whether speech
is commercial two relevant considerations are advertising format and
economic motivation. (Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. at pp. 66-67.) These
considerations imply that commercial speech generally or typically
is directed to an audience of persons who may be influenced by that
speech to engage in a commercial transaction with the speaker or the
person on whose behalf the speaker is acting. Speech in advertising
format typically, although not invariably, is speech about a product
or service by a person who is offering that product or service at a
price, directed to persons [27 Cal.4th 961] who may want, and be willing
to pay for, that product or service. Citing New York Times v. Sullivan,
supra, 376 U.S. 254, which concerned a newspaper advertisement seeking
contributions for civil rights causes, the court cautioned, however,
that presentation in advertising format does not necessarily establish
that a message is commercial in character. (Bolger, supra, at p. 66.)
Economic motivation likewise implies that the speech is intended to
lead to commercial transactions, which in turn assumes that the speaker
and the target audience are persons who will engage in those transactions,
or their agents or intermediaries.
Finally, the factual content of the message should be
commercial in character. In the context of regulation
of false or
misleading advertising,
this typically means that the speech consists of representations
of fact about the business operations, products, or services
of the speaker
(or the individual or company that the speaker represents),
made for the purpose of promoting sales of, or other
commercial transactions
in, the speaker's products or services. This is consistent
with, and
implicit in, the United States Supreme Court's commercial
speech decisions, each of which has involved statements
about a product
or service, or
about the operations or qualifications of the person
offering the product or service. (See, e.g., Rubin v.
Coors Brewing
Co., supra,
514 U.S.
476 [statement of alcohol content on beer bottle label];
Ibanez v. Florida Dept. of Business & Professional
Regulation, Bd. of Accountancy, supra, 512 U.S. 136 [statements
on an
attorney's letterhead and business
cards describing attorney's qualifications]; Va. Pharmacy
Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council, supra, 425 U.S. 748 [advertisements
showing
prices
of prescription drugs].)
This is also consistent with the third Bolger factor--product
references. By "product references," we do not understand the United
States Supreme Court to mean only statements about the price, qualities,
or availability of individual items offered for sale. Rather, we understand "product
references" to include also, for example, statements about the
manner in which the products are manufactured, distributed, or sold,
about repair or warranty services that the seller provides to purchasers
of the product, or about the identity or qualifications of persons
who manufacture, distribute, sell, service, or endorse the product.
Similarly, references to services would include not only statements
about the price, availability, and quality of the services themselves,
but also, for example, statements about the education, experience,
and qualifications of the persons providing or endorsing the services.
(See, e.g., Ibanez v. Florida Dept. of Business & Professional
Regulation, Bd. of Accountancy, supra, 512 U.S. 136 [statements on
an attorney's letterhead and business cards describing attorney's training
and qualifications].) This broad definition of "product references" is
necessary, we think, [27 Cal.4th 962] to adequately categorize
statements made in the context of a modern, sophisticated
public relations campaign
intended to increase sales and profits by enhancing the
image of a product or of its manufacturer or seller.
Our understanding of the content element of commercial
speech is also consistent with the reasons that the United
States
Supreme Court has
given for denying First Amendment protection to false
or misleading commercial speech. The high court has stated
that false or
misleading commercial speech may be prohibited because
the truth of commercial
speech is "more easily verifiable by its disseminator" and
because commercial speech, being motivated by the desire
for economic profit, is less likely than noncommercial
speech to
be chilled
by proper regulation. (Va. Pharmacy Bd. v. Va. Consumer
Council, supra,
425 U.S.
at p. 772, fn. 24.) This explanation assumes that commercial
speech consists of factual statements and that those
statements describe
matters within the personal knowledge of the speaker
or the person whom the
speaker is representing and are made for the purpose
of financial gain. Thus, this explanation implies that,
at
least in relation
to regulations
aimed at protecting consumers from false and misleading
promotional practices, commercial speech must consist
of factual representations
about the business operations, products, or services
of the speaker (or the individual or company on whose
behalf
the
speaker is
speaking), made for the purpose of promoting sales of,
or other commercial
transactions in, the speaker's products or services.
The United States Supreme
Court has never decided whether false statements about
a product or service
of a competitor of the speaker would properly be categorized
as commercial speech. Because the issue is not presented
here, we
offer no view
on how it should be resolved.
Apart from this consideration of the identities of the
speaker and the audience, and the contents of the speech,
we find
nothing in
the United States Supreme Court's commercial speech decisions
that is essential
to a determination that particular speech is commercial
in character in the context of a consumer protection
law intended
to suppress
false or deceptive commercial messages. Although in Bolger,
supra, 463 U.S.
60, the United States Supreme Court noted that the speech
at issue there was in a traditional advertising format,
the court
cautioned
that it was not holding that this factor would always
be necessary to the characterization of speech as commercial,
and in Leoni,
supra, 39 Cal.3d 609, this court held that an attorney's
mailings were commercial
speech even though they were not in the form of an advertisement.
(See also Ibanez v. Florida Dept. of Business & Professional
Regulation, Bd. of Accountancy, supra, 512 U.S. 136 [accepting
as commercial speech
statements on an attorney's letterhead and business cards].)
Thus, advertising format is by no means essential to
characterization as commercial speech. [27 Cal.4th 963]
[14] Here, the first element--a commercial speaker--is satisfied because
the speakers--Nike and its officers and directors--are engaged in commerce.
Specifically, they manufacture, import, distribute, and sell consumer
goods in the form of athletic shoes and apparel.
The second element--an intended commercial audience--is
also satisfied. Nike's letters to university presidents
and directors
of athletic
departments were addressed directly to actual and potential
purchasers of Nike's
products, because college and university athletic departments
are major purchasers of athletic shoes and apparel. Plaintiff
has alleged
that
Nike's press releases and letters to newspaper editors,
although addressed to the public generally, were also
intended to
reach and influence
actual and potential purchasers of Nike's products. Specifically,
plaintiff has alleged that Nike made these statements
about its labor policies
and practices "to maintain and/or increase its sales and profits." To
support this allegation, plaintiff has included as an exhibit a letter
to a newspaper editor, written by Nike's director of communications,
referring to Nike's labor policies practices and stating that "[c]onsumers
are savvy and want to know they support companies with good products
and practices" and that "[d]uring the shopping
season, we encourage shoppers to remember that Nike is
the industry's
leader in
improving factory conditions."
The third element--representations of fact of a commercial nature--is
also present. In describing its own labor policies, and the practices
and working conditions in factories where its products are made, Nike
was making factual representations about its own business operations.
In speaking to consumers about working conditions and labor practices
in the factories where its products are made, Nike addressed matters
within its own knowledge. The wages paid to the factories' employees,
the hours they work, the way they are treated, and whether the environmental
conditions under which they work violate local health and safety laws,
are all matters likely to be within the personal knowledge of Nike
executives, employees, or subcontractors. Thus, Nike was in a position
to readily verify the truth of any factual assertions it made on these
topics.
In speaking to consumers about working conditions in
the factories where its products are made, Nike engaged
in
speech that is
particularly hardy or durable. Because Nike's purpose
in making these statements,
at least as alleged in the first amended complaint, was
to maintain its sales and profits, regulation aimed at
preventing
false and
actually or inherently misleading speech is unlikely
to deter Nike from speaking
truthfully or at all about the conditions in its factories.
To the extent that application of these laws may make
Nike more
cautious, and cause it to make greater efforts to verify
the [27 Cal.4th
964]
truth of its statements, these laws will serve the purpose
of commercial speech protection by "insuring that the stream of commercial information
flow[s] cleanly as well as freely." (Va. Pharmacy
Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council, supra, 425 U.S. at pp. 772.)
Finally, government regulation of Nike's speech about
working conditions in factories where Nike products are
made is
consistent with traditional
government authority to regulate commercial transactions
for the protection of consumers by preventing false and
misleading commercial
practices.
Trade regulation laws have traditionally sought to suppress
and prevent not only false or misleading statements about
products
or services
in themselves but also false or misleading statements
about where
a product was made (see § 17533.7 [making it unlawful to sell a
product falsely labeled as "Made in U.S.A."]; 15 U.S.C. § 1125(a)
[allowing damages for "false designation of origin"]), or
by whom (see § 17520 et seq. [prohibiting false representation
of product as made by blind workers]; § 17569 [prohibiting false
representation of product "as made by authentic American Indian
labor or workmanship"]; Lab. Code, § 1010 et
seq. [prohibiting false labeling about the kind, character,
or
nature of labor
employed in product's manufacture]).
Because in the statements at issue here Nike was acting as a commercial
speaker, because its intended audience was primarily the buyers of
its products, and because the statements consisted of factual representations
about its own business operations, we conclude that the statements
were commercial speech for purposes of applying state laws designed
to prevent false advertising and other forms of commercial deception.
Whether these statements could properly be categorized as commercial
speech for some other purpose, and whether these statements could properly
be categorized as commercial speech if one or more of these elements
was not fully satisfied, are questions we need not decide here.
Nike argues that its allegedly false and misleading statements
were not commercial speech because they were part of "an international
media debate on issues of intense public interest." In a similar
vein, our dissenting colleagues argue that the speech at issue here
should not be categorized as commercial speech because, when Nike made
the statements defending its labor practices, the nature and propriety
of those practices had already become a matter of public interest and
public debate. (Dis. opn. of Chin, J., post, at p. 974; dis. opn. of
Brown, J., post, at pp. 980, 982-984.) This argument falsely assumes
that speech cannot properly be categorized as commercial speech if
it relates to a matter of significant public interest or controversy.
As the United States Supreme Court has explained, commercial speech
commonly concerns matters of intense public and private interest. [27
Cal.4th 965] The individual consumer's interest in the price, availability,
and characteristics of products and services "may be as keen,
if not keener by far, than his interest in the day's most urgent political
debate." (Va. Pharmacy Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council, supra, 425
U.S. at p. 763.) And for the public as whole, information on commercial
matters is "indispensable" not only "to the proper allocation
of resources in a free enterprise system" but also "to the
formation of intelligent opinions as to how that system ought to be
regulated or altered." (Id. at p. 765; see also Greater New Orleans
Broadcasting Assn., Inc. v. United States, supra, 527 U.S. at p. 184
[observing that the commercial speech at issue there concerned "an
activity that is the subject of intense debate in many communities"].)
In her dissent, Justice Brown states that our logic "erroneously
assumes that false or misleading commercial speech . . . can never
be speech about a public issue." (Dis. opn. of Brown, J., post,
at pp. 983-984.) On the contrary, we assume that commercial speech
frequently and even normally addresses matters of public concern. The
reason that it is "less necessary to tolerate inaccurate statements
for fear of silencing the speaker" of commercial speech is not
that such speech concerns matters of lesser public interest or value,
but rather that commercial speech is both "more easily verifiable
by its disseminator" and "less likely to be chilled by proper
regulation." (Va. Pharmacy Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council,
supra, 425 U.S. at p. 772, fn. 24; accord, Lorillard
Tobacco Co. v. Reilly,
supra, 533 U.S. at p. __ [121 S.Ct. at p. 2433].)
In support of their argument that speech about issues of public importance
or controversy must be considered noncommercial speech, our dissenting
colleagues cite Thomas v. Collins (1945) 323 U.S. 516, and Thornhill
v. State of Alabama (1940) 310 U.S. 88. The United States Supreme Court
issued these decisions three decades before it developed the modern
commercial speech doctrine in Bigelow v. Virginia, supra, 421 U.S.
809, and Va. Pharmacy Bd. V. Va. Consumer Council, supra, 425 U.S.
748. Moreover, neither decision addressed the validity of a law prohibiting
false or misleading speech. To the extent they hold that truthful and
nonmisleading speech about commercial matters of public importance
is entitled to constitutional protection, they are consistent with
the modern commercial speech doctrine and with the decision we reach
today. We find nothing in either decision suggesting that the state
lacks the authority to prohibit false and misleading factual representations,
made for purposes of maintaining and increasing sales and profits,
about the speaker's own products, services, or business operations.
For purposes of categorizing Nike's speech as commercial
or noncommercial, it does not matter that Nike was responding
to charges publicly
raised [27 Cal.4th 966] by others and was thereby participating
in a public
debate. The point is illustrated by a decision of a federal
court of appeals about statements by a trade association
denying
there
was scientific
evidence that eating eggs increased the risk of heart
and circulatory disease. (National Commission on Egg
Nutrition
v. Federal Trade
Commission (7th Cir. 1977) 570 F.2d 157, 159, cert. den.
(1978) 439 U.S. 821.)
The court held that these statement were commercial speech
subject to regulation by the Federal Trade Commission
(FTC) to the extent
the statements were false or misleading, even though
the trade association made the statements "to counteract what the FTC described as 'anti-cholesterol
attacks on eggs which had resulted in steadily declining per capita
egg consumption.' " (Id. at p. 159.) Responding to the argument
that the statements were noncommercial because they concerned a debate
on a matter of great public interest, the federal court of appeals
responded that "the right of government to restrain false advertising
can hardly depend upon the view of an agency or court as to the relative
importance of the issue to which the false advertising relates." (Id.
at p. 163.)
Here, Nike's speech is not removed from the category
of commercial speech because it is intermingled with
noncommercial
speech.
To the extent Nike's press releases and letters discuss
policy questions
such as the degree to which domestic companies should
be responsible for
working conditions in factories located in other countries,
or what
standards domestic companies ought to observe in such
factories, or the merits and effects of economic "globalization" generally,
Nike's statements are noncommercial speech. Any content-based regulation
of these noncommercial messages would be subject to the strict scrutiny
test for fully protected speech. (See, e.g., Consolidated Edison Co.
v. Public Serv. Comm'n, supra, 447 U.S. 530.) But Nike may not "immunize
false or misleading product information from government regulation
simply by including references to public issues." (Bolger,
supra, 463 U.S. at p. 68, fn. omitted.) Here, the alleged
false and misleading
statements all relate to the commercial portions of the
speech in question--the description of actual conditions
and practices
in factories
that produce
Nike's products--and thus the proposed regulations reach
only that commercial portion.
Asserting that the commercial and noncommercial elements
in Nike's statement were "inextricably intertwined," our dissenting
colleagues maintain that it must therefore be categorized as noncommercial
speech, and they cite in support the United States Supreme Court's
decision in Riley v. National Federation of the Blind of North Carolina
(1988) 487 U.S. 781 (Riley). That decision concerned regulation of
charitable solicitations, a category of speech that does not fit within
our limited-purpose [27 Cal.4th 967] definition of commercial speech
because it does not involve factual representations about a product
or service that is offered for sale. More importantly, the high court
has since explained that in Riley "the commercial speech (if it
was that) was 'inextricably intertwined' because the state law required
it to be included" and that commercial and noncommercial messages
are not "inextricable" unless there is some
legal or practical compulsion to combine them. (Board
of Trustees,
State
Univ. of N.Y.
v. Fox, supra, 492 U.S. at p. 474, italics omitted.)
No law required Nike to combine factual representations
about
its
own labor practices
with expressions of opinion about economic globalization,
nor was it impossible for Nike to address those subjects
separately.
We also reject Nike's argument that regulating its speech
to suppress false and misleading statements is impermissible
because
it would
restrict or disfavor expression of one point of view
(Nike's) and not the other
point of view (that of the critics of Nike's labor practices).
The argument is misdirected because the regulations in
question do not
suppress points of view but instead suppress false and
misleading statements of fact. As we have explained,
to the extent Nike's
speech represents
expression of opinion or points of view on general policy
questions such as the value of economic "globalization," it
is noncommercial speech subject to full First Amendment
protection. Nike's speech
loses that full measure of protection only when it concerns
facts
material
to commercial transactions--here, factual statements
about how Nike makes its products.
Moreover, differential treatment of speech about products
and services based on the identity of the speaker is
inherent in
the commercial
speech doctrine as articulated by the United States Supreme
Court. A noncommercial speaker's statements criticizing
a product are
generally noncommercial speech, for which damages may
be awarded only upon
proof of both falsehood and actual malice. (See, e.g.,
Bose Corp. v. Consumers
Union of U.S., Inc., supra, 466 U.S. at p. 513 [so treating
unflattering statements in a consumer magazine's review
of high fidelity speakers].)
A commercial speaker's statements in praise or support
of the same product, by comparison, are commercial speech
that
may
be prohibited
entirely to the extent the statements are either false
or actually or inherently misleading. (In re R.M.J.,
supra, 455 U.S. at
p. 203.) To repeat, the justification for this different
treatment, as the
high court has explained, is that when a speaker promotes
its own products,
it is "less necessary to tolerate inaccurate statements for fear
of silencing the speaker" because the described speech is both "more
easily verifiable by its disseminator" and "less likely to
be chilled by proper regulation." (Va. Pharmacy
Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council, supra, 425 U.S. at p. 772,
fn.
24; [27
Cal.4th
968] accord,
Lorillard Tobacco Co. v. Reilly, supra, 533 U.S. at p.
__ [121 S.Ct. at p. 2433].)
Our dissenting colleagues are correct that the identity of the speaker
is usually not a proper consideration in regulating speech that is
entitled to First Amendment protection, and that a valid regulation
of protected speech may not handicap one side of a public debate. But
to decide whether a law regulating speech violates the First Amendment,
the very first question is whether the speech that the law regulates
is entitled to First Amendment protection at all. As we have seen,
commercial speech that is false or misleading receives no protection
under the First Amendment, and therefore a law that prohibits only
such unprotected speech cannot violate constitutional free speech provisions.
We conclude, accordingly, that here the trial court and the Court of
Appeal erred in characterizing as noncommercial speech, under the First
Amendment to the federal Constitution, Nike's allegedly false and misleading
statements about labor practices and working conditions in factories
where Nike products are made.
We now disapprove as ill-considered dicta two statements
of this court in Spiritual Psychic Science Church v.
City of Azusa
(1985)
39 Cal.3d
501. There we remarked that commercial speech is speech "which
has but one purpose--to advance an economic transaction," and
we suggested that "an advertisement informing the public that
the cherries for sale at store X were picked by union workers" would
be noncommercial speech. (Id. at p. 511.)
As we have explained, the United States Supreme Court
has indicated that economic motivation is relevant but
not
conclusive and
perhaps not even necessary. (Bolger, supra, 463 U.S.
at p. 67 & fn.
14.) The high court has never held that commercial speech
must have as
its only purpose the advancement of an economic transaction,
and it has
explained instead that commercial speech may be intermingled
with noncommercial speech. (Id. at pp. 67-68.) An advertisement
primarily
intended to
reach consumers and to influence them to buy the speaker's
products is not exempt from the category of commercial
speech because
the speaker also has a secondary purpose to influence
lenders, investors,
or lawmakers.
Nor is speech exempt from the category of commercial speech because
it relates to the speaker's labor practices rather than to the price,
availability, or quality of the speaker's goods. An advertisement to
the public that [27 Cal.4th 969] cherries were picked by union workers
is commercial speech if the speaker has a financial or commercial interest
in the sale of the cherries and if the information that the cherries
had been picked by union workers is likely to influence consumers to
buy the speaker's cherries. Speech is commercial in its content if
it is likely to influence consumers in their commercial decisions.
For a significant segment of the buying public, labor practices do
matter in making consumer choices.
B. The California Constitution
In the few cases in which this court has addressed the distinction
between commercial and noncommercial speech, we have not articulated
a separate test for determining what constitutes commercial speech
under the state Constitution, but instead we have used the tests fashioned
by the United States Supreme Court. For example, in Leoni, supra, 39
Cal.3d 609, we used the three-factor test the high court had articulated
in Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. 60, and we concluded that the speech in
question was commercial speech because two of the three factors were
present. So also here, we perceive no need to articulate a separate
test for commercial speech under the state Constitution. Having concluded
that the speech at issue is commercial speech under the federal Constitution,
we now reach the same conclusion under the California Constitution.
V. CONCLUSION
As the United States Supreme Court has explained, false and misleading
speech has no constitutional value in itself and is protected only
in circumstances and to the extent necessary to give breathing room
for the free debate of public issues. Commercial speech, because it
is both more readily verifiable by its speaker and more hardy than
noncommercial speech, can be effectively regulated to suppress false
and actually or inherently misleading messages without undue risk of
chilling public debate. With these basic principles in mind, we conclude
that when a corporation, to maintain and increase its sales and profits,
makes public statements defending labor practices and working conditions
at factories where its products are made, those public statements are
commercial speech that may be regulated to prevent consumer deception.
Sprinkled with references to a series of children's books about wizardry
and sorcery, Justice Brown's dissent itself tries to find the magic
formula or incantation that will transform a business enterprise's
factual representations in defense of its own products and profits
into noncommercial speech exempt from our state's consumer protection
laws. As we have explained, [27 Cal.4th 970] however, such representations,
when aimed at potential buyers for the purpose of maintaining sales
and profits, may be regulated to eliminate false and misleading statements
because they are readily verifiable by the speaker and because regulation
is unlikely to deter truthful and nonmisleading speech.
In concluding, contrary to the Court of Appeal, that Nike's speech
at issue here is commercial speech, we do not decide whether that speech
was, as plaintiff has alleged, false or misleading, nor do we decide
whether plaintiff's complaint is vulnerable to demurrer for reasons
not considered here. Because the demurrers of Nike and the individual
defendants were based on multiple grounds, further proceedings on the
demurrers may be required in the Court of Appeal, the superior court,
or both. Our decision on the narrow issue before us on review does
not foreclose those proceedings.
The judgment of the Court of Appeal is reversed, and the matter is
remanded to that court for further proceedings consistent with this
opinion.
George, C. J., Werdegar, J., and Moreno, J., concurred.
CHIN, J., Dissenting:
I respectfully dissent.
Nike, Inc. (Nike), is a major international corporation with a
multibillion dollar enterprise. The nature of its labor
practices has become a
subject of considerable public interest and scrutiny.
Various persons and organizations
have accused Nike of engaging in despicable practices,
which they have described sometimes with such caustic and scathing
words as "slavery" and "sweatshop." Nike's
critics and these accusations receive full First Amendment protection.
And well they should. "The First and Fourteenth Amendments embody
our 'profound national commitment to the principle that debate on public
issues should be uninhibited, robust, and wide-open . . . .' " (Garrison
v. Louisiana (1964) 379 U.S. 64, 75 (Garrison), quoting New York Times
Co. v. Sullivan (1964) 376 U.S. 254, 270.) "Under the First Amendment
there is no such thing as a false idea. However pernicious an opinion
may seem, we depend for its correction not on the conscience of judges
and juries but on the competition of other ideas." (Gertz
v. Robert Welch, Inc. (1974) 418 U.S. 323, 339-340, fn.
omitted.)
While Nike's critics have taken full advantage of their
right to " 'uninhibited,
robust, and wide-open' " debate (Garrison, supra, 379 U.S. at
p. 75), the same cannot be said of Nike, the object of their ire. [27
Cal.4th 971] When Nike tries to defend itself from these attacks, the
majority denies it the same First Amendment protection Nike's critics
enjoy. Why is this, according to the majority? Because Nike competes
not only in the marketplace of ideas, but also in the marketplace of
manufactured goods. And because Nike sells shoes--and its defense against
critics may help sell those shoes--the majority asserts that Nike may
not freely engage in the debate, but must run the risk of lawsuits
under California's unfair competition law (Bus. & Prof. Code, § 17200
et seq.) and false advertising law (Bus. & Prof. Code, § 17500
et seq.), should it ever make a factual claim that turns
out to be inaccurate. According to the majority, if Nike
utters
a factual
misstatement,
unlike its critics, it may be sued for restitution, civil
penalties, and injunctive relief under these sweeping
statutes. (Maj.
opn., ante, at pp. 949-951.)
Handicapping one side in this important worldwide debate
is both ill considered and unconstitutional. Full free
speech protection
for one
side and strict liability for the other will hardly promote
vigorous and meaningful debate. "Debate on public issues will not be uninhibited
if the speaker must run the risk that it will be proved in court that
he spoke out of hatred; even if he did speak out of hatred, utterances
honestly believed contribute to the free interchange of ideas and the
ascertainment of truth." (Garrison, supra, 379 U.S. at p. 73.)
The state, "even with the purest of motives, may not substitute
its judgment as to how best to speak for that of speakers and listeners;
free and robust debate cannot thrive if directed by the government." (Riley
v. National Federation of Blind (1988) 487 U.S. 781,
791 (Riley).)
In its pursuit to regulate Nike's speech--in hope of
prohibiting false and misleading statements--the majority
has unduly
trammeled basic
constitutional freedoms that form the foundation of this
free government. fn. 1 "[W]here . . . suppression of speech suggests an attempt
to give one side of a debatable public question an advantage in expressing
its views to the people, the First Amendment is plainly offended." (First
National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti (1978) 435 U.S. 765,
785-786 (Bellotti), fn. omitted.)
I. IRRESPECTIVE OF NIKE'S ECONOMIC MOTIVATION, THE PUBLIC HAS A RIGHT
TO RECEIVE INFORMATION ON MATTERS OF PUBLIC CONCERN
The United States Supreme Court has emphasized that economic
motivation--in this case, Nike's desire to sell athletic
products--is not a dispositive
[27 Cal.4th 972] factor in determining whether certain
speech is commercial. (Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products
Corp. (1983)
463 U.S.
60, 67 (Bolger).)
In deciding the scope of the constitutional protection
of corporate speech, the high court struck down a Massachusetts
criminal
statute that proscribed corporations from giving campaign
contributions to influence the vote on a referendum materially
affecting
the
corporation's
property, business, or assets. (Bellotti, supra, 435
U.S. 765.) Corporate speech, the high court noted, did
not deserve
less
protection simply
because of its source. "The question in this case, simply put,
is whether the corporate identity of the speaker deprives this proposed
speech of what otherwise would be its clear entitlement to protection." (Id.
at p. 778.) In Nike's case, based on the majority's holding,
it does.
As the Court of Appeal below noted, given Nike's powerful
corporate image and industry stronghold, the private
company "exemplifi[ed]
the perceived evils or benefits of labor practices associated with
the processes of economic globalization." Nike, in effect, became
the "poster child" in the international campaign for labor
rights and reform (see, e.g., Note, Now Playing: Corporate Codes of
Conduct in the Global Theater: Is Nike Just Doing It? (1998) 15 Ariz.
J. Intl. & Comp. L. 905), and Nike's labor practices
became relevant in a much broader and public context.
Though expressions
on labor
disputes have been afforded full First Amendment protection
(see Va. Pharmacy
Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council (1976) 425 U.S. 748, 762
(Va. Pharmacy Bd.), and cited cases; Thornhill v. Alabama
(1940)
310 U.S.
88, 101-103 (Thornhill)), the majority loses sight of
the full protections
afforded
this speech in the face of Nike's corporate identity.
(Bellotti, supra, 435 U.S. at p. 778.) And because of
this myopia,
the public loses.
The public at large, in addition to Nike's actual and
intended customers, has the right to receive information
from both
sides of this international
debate. "Freedom of speech presupposes a willing speaker. But
where a speaker exists . . . the protection afforded is to the communication,
to its source and to its recipients both." (Va. Pharmacy Bd.,
supra, 425 U.S. at p. 756, fn. omitted.) The First Amendment serves
an "informational purpose" that guarantees "the public
access to discussion, debate, and the dissemination of information
and ideas." (Bellotti, supra, 435 U.S. at p. 782,
fn. 18; id. at p. 783; see Bigelow v. Virginia (1975)
421 U.S.
809, 822
(Bigelow).)
Thus, not only Nike, but all of us, are the poorer for
the majority's assault on free speech. [27 Cal.4th 973]
In striking down Virginia's attempt to ban a newspaper
advertisement announcing the availability of legal New
York abortions,
the high court noted: "The advertisement . . . did more than simply propose a
commercial transaction. It contained factual material of clear 'public
interest.' Portions of its message . . . involve the exercise of the
freedom of communicating information and disseminating opinion. [¶]
Viewed in its entirety, the advertisement conveyed information of potential
interest and value to a diverse audience--not only to readers possibly
in need of the services offered, but also to those with a general curiosity
about, or genuine interest in, the subject matter or the law of another
State and its development, and to readers seeking reform in Virginia.
. . . Thus, in this case, appellant's First Amendment interests coincided
with the constitutional interests of the general public." (Bigelow,
supra, 421 U.S. at p. 822, fn. omitted, italics added; Jacoby v. State
Bar (1977) 19 Cal.3d 359, 370-371 [following Bigelow]; cf. Bolger,
supra, 463 U.S. at p. 68 [company may not "immunize false or misleading
product information from government regulation simply by including
references to public issues"].)
Here, Nike's statements regarding its labor practices
in China, Thailand, and Indonesia provided vital information
on the very
public controversy
concerning using low-cost foreign labor to manufacture
goods sold in America. Nike's responses defended against
adverse
reports that
its
overseas manufacturers committed widespread labor, health,
and safety law violations. Far from promoting the sale
of its athletic
products,
Nike did not include this information through product
labels,
inserts, packaging, or commercial advertising intended
to reach only Nike's
actual or potential customers. Rather, Nike responded
to the negative publicity through press releases, letters
to newspapers,
and letters
to university presidents and athletic directors. (Cf.
Bolger,
supra, 463 U.S. 60 [contraceptive manufacturer's informational
pamphlets
included with advertisements deemed commercial speech].)
To the extent Nike
may have been financially motivated to defend its business
and livelihood against these attacks, this motivation
is not dispositive
in identifying
speech as commercial. (Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. at p.
67.) "Viewed
in its entirety, [Nike's speech] conveyed information of potential
interest and value to a diverse audience . . . ." (Bigelow,
supra, 421 U.S. at p. 822.)
II. NIKE'S SPEECH IS NOT TRADITIONAL COMMERCIAL SPEECH
Indeed, characterizing Nike's speech here as commercial speech
is inconsistent with the high court's constitutional
jurisprudence for
yet another
[27 Cal.4th 974] reason. fn. 2 The high court has stated
that traditional commercial speech is speech that " 'does "no more than propose
a commercial transaction." ' " (Va. Pharmacy Bd., supra,
425 U.S. at p. 762; Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. at p. 66; see also Board
of Trustees, State Univ. of N. Y. v. Fox (1989) 492 U.S. 469, 473;
Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary Counsel (1985) 471 U.S. 626, 637;
but see Central Hudson Gas & Elec. v. Public Serv. Comm'n, supra,
447 U.S. at p. 561 [commercial speech is "expression related solely
to the economic interests of the speaker and its audience"].)
In this case, Nike's speech here went beyond proposing a commercial
transaction. It provided information vital to the public debate on
international labor rights and reform. As the Court of Appeal below
observed, "[i]nformation about the labor practices
at Nike's overseas plants . . . constitute[d] data relevant
to a controversy
of great
public interest in our times."
Contrary to the majority's assertions (see maj. opn.,
ante, at p. 966), the high court's restriction--" 'advertising which "links
a product to a current public debate" is not thereby entitled
to the constitutional protection afforded noncommercial speech' " (Bolger,
supra, 463 U.S. at p. 68)--does not apply here. In Bolger, the informational
mailings, though containing issues of public concern such as venereal
disease and family planning, were at bottom commercial speech directed
at selling contraceptives. (Id. at p. 66.) The court made clear that
most of the mailings fell "within the core notion of commercial
speech--'speech which does "no more than propose a commercial
transaction." ' " (Ibid.) To the extent that some mailings
discussed public concerns, the high court cautioned that "[a]dvertisers
should not be permitted to immunize false or misleading product information
from government regulation simply by including references to public
issues." (Id. at p. 68.)
In a case decided before Bolger, the high court held
that a utility company's monthly electric bill inserts
advocating
the use of
nuclear power, could [27 Cal.4th 975] not be regulated
under the First
and Fourteenth Amendments. (Consolidated Edison Co. v.
Public Serv. Comm'n
(1980) 447 U.S. 530 (Consolidated Edison).) In Consolidated
Edison, the high court did not address whether the inserts
constituted
commercial speech. Rather, it concluded that the utility
commission's
regulation
banning the inserts "limited the means by which Consolidated Edison
may participate in the public debate on this question and other controversial
issues of national interest and importance. Thus, the Commission's
prohibition of discussion of controversial issues strikes at the heart
of the freedom to speak." (Id. at p. 535.) Despite
Consolidated Edison's obvious economic incentive in promoting
the use
of nuclear power, the high court did not consider, must
less determine,
whether the inserts placed in electric bills amounted
to commercial speech.
The high court's concern in Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. 60,
therefore, was that advertisers refrain from inserting
information on
public issues as a pretext to avoid regulations governing
their commercial
speech.
fn. 3 That is simply not the case here. Nike's speech--in
the form of press releases and letters defending against
accusations
about
its overseas labor practices--was not in any sense pretextual,
but prompted
and necessitated by public criticism. As noted, Nike
did not use product labels, packaging, advertising, or
other
media
intended to directly
reach its actual or potential customers. Nike's speech
did not "simply
. . . include[] references to public issues." (Bolger, supra,
463 U.S. at p. 68.) Nike's labor practices and policies, and in turn,
its products, were the public issue. Its "discussion of controversial
issues strikes at the heart of the freedom to speak." (Consolidated
Edison, supra, 447 U.S. at p. 535.)
At the very least, this case typifies the circumstance
where commercial speech and noncommercial speech are "inextricably intertwined." (Riley,
supra, 487 U.S. at p. 796.) In Riley, the high court held that a North
Carolina statute regulating solicitation of charitable contributions
affected protected speech and was not narrowly tailored to meet the
state's interest in protecting charities from fraud. (Id. at p. 789.)
As relevant here, the court observed that even if a professional fundraiser's
speech amounted to commercial speech, "we do not [27 Cal.4th 976]
believe that the speech retains its commercial character when it is
inextricably intertwined with otherwise fully protected speech." (Id.
at p. 796.) It further held that "where, as here, the component
parts of a single speech are inextricably intertwined, we cannot parcel
out the speech, applying one test to one phrase and another test to
another phrase. Such an endeavor would be both artificial and impractical.
Therefore, we apply our test for fully protected expression." (Ibid.)
Notwithstanding the fact that Riley dealt with charitable
solicitations, which are not involved in this case, the
high court relied,
in part, on a case that provides insight here. (Riley,
supra, 487
U.S. at
p. 796, citing Thomas v. Collins (1945) 323 U.S. 516,
540-541 (Thomas).) In Thomas, which did not deal with
solicitation
of property or
funds, the high court addressed the issue whether a union
organizer's speech
soliciting members was protected by the First Amendment,
and whether a registration requirement in order to speak
was constitutionally
impermissible.
(Thomas, supra, 323 U.S. at pp. 533-534.) Answering yes
to both questions, the high court cautioned that a state's
regulation, "whether aimed
at fraud or other abuses, must not trespass upon the domain set apart
for free speech and free assembly. This Court has recognized that 'in
the circumstances of our times the dissemination of information concerning
the facts of a labor dispute must be regarded as within that area of
free discussion that is guaranteed by the Constitution. . . . Free
discussion concerning the conditions in industry and the causes of
labor disputes appears to us indispensable to the effective and intelligent
use of the processes of popular government to shape the destiny of
modern industrial society.' " (Id. at p. 532, quoting
Thornhill, supra, 310 U.S. at pp. 102, 103.) fn. 4
This case resembles Thomas in that Nike's speech provided
information " 'concerning
the conditions in [the manufacturing] industry' " and
thereby used
"
'the processes of popular government to shape the destiny of modern
industrial society.' [Citation.]" (Thomas, supra, 323 U.S. at
p. 532, quoting Thornhill, supra, 310 U.S. at p. 102.) Nike, which
came to the forefront of the international labor abuse debate, provided
relevant information about its labor practices in its overseas plants.
[27 Cal.4th 977] Nike's speech, in an attempt to influence public opinion
on economic globalization and international labor rights and working
conditions, gave the public insight and perspective into the debate.
This speech should be fully protected as "essential to free government." (Thornhill,
supra, 310 U.S. at p. 95.)
The majority's attempt to parse out Nike's noncommercial
speech--"to
the extent Nike's speech represents expression of opinion or points
of view on general policy questions . . . it is noncommercial speech" (maj.
opn., ante, at p. 967, italics added)--is both unavailing and unhelpful.
Even assuming that Nike's factual statements regarding how its products
are made constitute commercial speech, that speech is "inextricably
intertwined" with its noncommercial speech. (Riley, supra, 487
U.S. at p. 796.) Contrary to the majority's suggestion (maj. opn.,
ante, at pp. 966-967), Nike realistically could not discuss its general
policy on employee rights and working conditions and its views on economic
globalization without reference to the labor practices of its overseas
manufacturers, Nike products, and how they are made. Attempting to
parse out the commercial speech from the noncommercial speech in this
context "would be both artificial and impractical." (Riley,
supra, 487 U.S. at p. 796)
III. CONCLUSION
The majority today refuses to honor a fundamental commitment and
guarantee that both sides in a public debate may compete
vigorously--and equally--in
the marketplace of ideas. The First Amendment ensures
the freedom to speak on matters of public interest by both sides,
not just
one judicially
favored. (Bellotti, supra, 435 U.S. at pp. 785-786.)
Sadly,
Nike is not the only one who loses here--the public does,
too. "Those
who won our independence had confidence in the power of free and fearless
reasoning and communication of ideas to discover and spread political
and economic truth. Noxious doctrines in those fields may be refuted
and their evil averted by the courageous exercise of the right of free
discussion." (Thornhill, supra, 310 U.S. at p. 95.)
Because I would give both sides in this important public controversy
the full protection that our Constitution guarantees, I respectfully
dissent.
Baxter, J., concurred.
BROWN, J., Dissenting:
I respectfully dissent.
I
In 1942, the United States Supreme Court, like a wizard trained
at Hogwarts, waved its wand and "plucked the commercial doctrine
out of thin [27 Cal.4th 978] air." (Kozinski & Banner, Who's
Afraid of Commercial Speech (1990) 76 Va. L.Rev. 627, 627.) Unfortunately,
the court's doctrinal wizardry has created considerable confusion over
the past 60 years as it has struggled to define the difference between
commercial and noncommercial speech. The United States Supreme Court
has, in recent years, acknowledged "the difficulty of drawing
bright lines that will clearly cabin commercial speech in a distinct
category." (City of Cincinnati v. Discovery Network, Inc. (1993)
507 U.S. 410, 419 (Discovery Network).) After tracing the various definitions
of commercial speech used over the years, the court conceded that no "categorical
definition of the difference between" commercial and noncommercial
speech exists. (Id. at pp. 420-423.) Instead, the difference is a matter
of " 'common[]sense' " (Ohralik v. Ohio State Bar Assn. (1978)
436 U.S. 447, 455-456 (Ohralik)), and restrictions on speech "must
be examined carefully to ensure that speech deserving of greater constitutional
protection is not inadvertently suppressed." (Bolger v. Youngs
Drug Products Corp. (1983) 463 U.S. 60, 66, fn. omitted (Bolger).)
Consistent with these pronouncements, the United States Supreme Court
has expressly refused to define the elements of commercial speech.
(See id. at p. 67, fn. 14.) Indeed, "the impossibility of specifying
the parameters that define the category of commercial speech has haunted
its jurisprudence and scholarship." (Post, The Constitutional
Status of Commercial Speech (2000) 48 UCLA L.Rev. 1,
7.)
Despite this chaos, the majority, ostensibly guided by
Bolger, has apparently divined a new and simpler test
for commercial
speech. Under this "limited-purpose test," "categorizing a particular
statement as commercial or noncommercial speech requires consideration
of three elements: the speaker, the intended audience, and the content
of the message." (Maj. opn., ante, at p. 960.) Unfortunately,
the majority has forgotten the teachings of H.L. Mencken: "every
human problem" has a "solution" that is "neat,
plausible, and wrong." (Mencken, Prejudices: Second
Series (1977 reprint) p. 148.) Like the purported discovery
of cold
fusion over
a decade ago, the majority's test for commercial speech
promises much, but solves nothing. Instead of clarifying
the commercial
speech doctrine,
the test violates fundamental principles of First Amendment
jurisprudence by making the level of protection given
speech dependent on the
identity of the speaker--and not just the speech's content--and
by stifling
the ability of certain speakers to participate in the
public debate. In doing so, the majority unconstitutionally
favors
some speakers
over others and conflicts with the decisions of other
courts.
Contrary to the majority's belief, our current First
Amendment jurisprudence defies any simple solution. Under
the commercial
speech doctrine
[27 Cal.4th 979] currently propounded by the United States
Supreme Court,
all speech is either commercial or noncommercial, and
commercial speech receives less protection than noncommercial
speech.
(Central Hudson
Gas & Ele. Corp. v. Public Serv. Comm'n (1980) 447 U.S. 557, 562-563
(Central Hudson).) The doctrine further assumes that all commercial
speech is the same under the First Amendment. Thus, all commercial
speech receives the same level of lesser protection. The state may
therefore ban all commercial speech "that is fraudulent or deceptive
without further justification" (Edenfield v. Fane (1993) 507 U.S.
761, 768), but may not do the same to fraudulent or deceptive speech
in " 'matters of public concern' " (Dun & Bradstreet,
Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders (1985) 472 U.S. 749, 758-759 (plur. opn.
of Powell, J.) (Dun & Bradstreet), quoting First
National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti (1978) 435 U.S. 765,
776 (Bellotti)).
This simple categorization presupposes that commercial
speech is wholly distinct from noncommercial speech and
that all
commercial speech has
the same value under the First Amendment. The reality,
however, is quite different. With the growth of commercialism,
the
politicization of commercial interests, and the increasing
sophistication
of commercial
advertising over the past century, the gap between commercial
and noncommercial speech is rapidly shrinking. As several
commentators have observed,
examples of the intersection between commercial speech
and various forms of noncommercial speech, including
scientific, political
and
religious speech, abound. (See, e.g., Kozinski & Banner,
Who's Afraid of Commercial Speech, supra, 76 Va. L.Rev.
at pp. 639-648;
Redish, Product Health Claims and the First Amendment:
Scientific Expression
and the Twilight Zone of Commercial Speech (1990) 43
Vand. L.Rev. 1433, 1449-1454.) Indeed, the recent commissioning
of a Fay Weldon
novel
by the jewelry company Bulgari as a marketing ploy highlights
this blurring of commercial and noncommercial speech.
(See
Arnold, Making
Books: Placed Products, and Their Cost, N.Y. Times (Sept.
13, 2001) p. E3, col. 1.)
Although the world has become increasingly commercial,
the dichotomous nature of the commercial speech doctrine
remains
unchanged. The
classification of speech as commercial or noncommercial
determines the level of
protection accorded to that speech under the First Amendment.
Thus, the majority
correctly characterizes the issue as "whether defendant corporation's
false statements are commercial or noncommercial speech for purposes
of constitutional free speech analysis under the state and federal
Constitutions." (Maj. opn., ante, at p. 946.) If
Nike's press releases, letters [27 Cal.4th 980] and other
documents
are commercial
speech, then the application of Business and Professions
Code sections 17204 and 17535 fn. 1 --which establish
strict liability
for false
and misleading ads--is constitutional. Otherwise, it
is not.
Constrained by this rigid dichotomy, I dissent because
Nike's statements are more like noncommercial speech
than commercial
speech. Nike's
commercial statements about its labor practices cannot
be separated from its noncommercial
statements about a public issue, because its labor practices
are the public issue. Indeed, under the circumstances
presented in
this case,
Nike could hardly engage in a general discussion on overseas
labor exploitation and economic globalization without
discussing its
own labor practices. (See Thomas v. Collins (1945) 323
U.S. 516, 534-535.)
Thus, the commercial elements of Nike's statements are "inextricably
intertwined" with their noncommercial elements. (Riley v. National
Federation of Blind (1988) 487 U.S. 781, 796 (Riley).) This court should
therefore "apply [the] test for fully protected expression," notwithstanding
the majority's specious distinctions of the relevant
case law. Under this test, a categorical ban on all false
and
misleading
statements
made by Nike about its labor practices violates the First
Amendment.
Although this result follows from controlling United
States Supreme Court precedent, I believe the commercial
speech
doctrine, in
its current form, fails to account for the realities
of the modern world--a world
in which personal, political, and commercial arenas no
longer have
sharply defined boundaries. My sentiments are not unique;
many judges and academics have echoed them. (See, e.g.,
Kozinski & Banner,
The Anti-History and Pre-History of Commercial Speech (1993) 71 Tex.
L.Rev. 747; Kozinski & Banner, Who's Afraid of Commercial Speech,
supra, 76 Va. L.Rev. at p. 627; Redish, The First Amendment in the
Marketplace: Commercial Speech and the Values of Free Expression (1971)
39 Geo. Wash. L.Rev. 429.) Even some justices on the high court have
recently questioned the validity of the distinction between commercial
and noncommercial speech. (See 44 Liquormart, Inc. v. Rhode Island
(1996) 517 U.S. 484, 522 (conc. opn. of Thomas, J.) ["I do not
see a philosophical or historical basis for asserting that 'commercial'
speech is of 'lower value' than 'noncommercial' speech"]; id.
at p. 517 (conc. opn. of Scalia, J.) ["I share Justice Thomas's
discomfort with the Central Hudson test"].) Nonetheless,
the high court has apparently declined to abandon it.
(See, e.g., Greater
New
Orleans Broadcasting Assn., Inc. v. United States (1999)
527 U.S. 173, 183 [27 Cal.4th 981] (Greater New Orleans
Broadcasting) [applying
the
Central Hudson test to restrictions on commercial speech].)
Given that the United States Supreme Court is not prepared
to start
over, we must
try to make the commercial speech doctrine work--warts
and all. To this end, I believe the high court needs
to develop
a more
nuanced approach that maximizes the ability of businesses
to
participate
in the public debate while minimizing consumer fraud.
II
According to the majority, all speech containing the following
three elements is commercial speech: (1) "a commercial speaker" (maj.
opn., ante, at p. 962); (2) "an intended commercial audience" (id.
at page 963.); and (3) "representations of fact of a commercial
nature" (ibid..). The first element is satisfied whenever the
speaker is engaged in "the production, distribution, or sale of
goods or services" "or someone acting on behalf of a person
so engaged." (Id. at p. 960.) The second element is satisfied
whenever the intended audience is "actual or potential buyers
or customers of the speaker's goods or services, or persons acting
for actual or potential buyers or customers, or persons (such as reporters
or reviewers) likely to repeat the message to or otherwise influence
actual or potential buyers or customers." (Ibid.) The third element
is satisfied whenever "the speech consists of representations
of fact about the business operations, products, or services of the
speaker (or the individual or company that the speaker represents),
made for the purpose of promoting sales of, or other commercial transactions
in, the speaker's products or services." (Id. at
p. 961.)
Although the majority constructed this limited-purpose
test from its "close
reading of the high court's commercial speech decisions" (maj.
opn., ante, at p. 960), it conveniently dismisses those
decisions that cast doubt on its formulation. As explained
below, a
closer review
of the relevant case law reveals that the majority's
test for commercial speech contravenes long-standing
principles
of First
Amendment
law.
First, the test flouts the very essence of the distinction
between commercial and noncommercial speech identified
by the United
States Supreme Court. "If commercial speech is to be distinguished, it
'must be distinguished by its content.' " (Bates
v. State Bar of Ariz. (1977) 433 U.S. 350, 363, italics
added
(Bates),
quoting Va. Pharmacy Bd. v. Va. Consumer Council (1976)
425 U.S. 748, 761
(Va.
Consumer Council).) Despite this caveat, the majority
distinguishes commercial from noncommercial speech using
two criteria
wholly unrelated
to the speech's content: the identity of the [27 Cal.4th
982] speaker and the intended audience. (See maj. opn.,
ante, at
p. 960.) In
doing so, the majority strays from the guiding principles
espoused by the
United States Supreme Court.
Second, the test contravenes a fundamental tenet of First
Amendment jurisprudence by making the identity of the
speaker potentially
dispositive. As the United States Supreme Court stated
long ago, "[the] identity
of the speaker is not decisive in determining whether speech is protected" (Pacific
Gas & Electric Co. v. Public Utilities Comm'n (1986) 475 U.S. 1,
8 (plur. opn. of Powell, J.) (Pacific Gas & Electric)), and "speech
does not lose its protection because of the corporate identity of the
speaker" (id. at p. 16). This is because corporations and other
speakers engaged in commerce "contribute to the 'discussion, debate,
and the dissemination of information and ideas' that the First Amendment
seeks to foster." (Id. at p. 8, quoting Bellotti, supra, 435 U.S.
at p. 783.) Thus, "[t]he inherent worth of the speech in terms
of its capacity for informing the public does not depend upon the identity
of its source, whether corporation, association, union, or individual." (Bellotti,
at p. 777, italics added.) Despite these admonitions, the majority
has made the identity of the speaker a significant, and potentially
dispositive, factor in determining the scope of protection accorded
to speech under the First Amendment. (See maj. opn., ante, at p. 960.)
As a result, speech by "someone engaged in commerce" may
receive less protection solely because of the speaker's identity. (Ibid.)
Indeed, the majority's limited-purpose test makes the identity of the
speaker dispositive whenever the speech at issue relates to the speaker's
business operations, products, or services, in contravention of United
States Supreme Court precedent. (See Pacific Gas & Electric,
supra, 475 U.S. at p. 8 (plur. opn. of Powell, J.).)
Third, the test violates the First Amendment by stifling
the ability of speakers engaged in commerce, such as
corporations, to participate
in debates over public issues. The United States Supreme
Court
has broadly defined public issues as those issues "about which information
is needed or appropriate to enable the members of society to cope with
the exigencies of their period." (Thornhill v. Alabama (1940)
310 U.S. 88, 102.) "The general proposition that freedom of expression
upon public questions is secured by the First Amendment has long been
settled . . . ." (New York Times Co. v. Sullivan (1964) 376 U.S.
254, 269 (New York Times).) "[S]peech on public issues occupies
the 'highest rung of the hierarchy of First Amendment values,' and
is entitled to special protection" (Connick v. Myers (1983) 461
U.S. 138, 145), [27 Cal.4th 983] because such speech "is more
than self-expression; it is the essence of self-government" (Garrison
v. Louisiana (1964) 379 U.S. 64, 74-75). "The First and Fourteenth
Amendments remove 'governmental restraints from the arena of public
discussion, putting the decision as to what views shall be voiced largely
into the hands of each of us, in the hope that use of such freedom
will ultimately produce a more capable citizenry and more perfect polity
. . . .' " (Consolidated Edison Co. v. Public Serv. Comm'n of
New York (1980) 447 U.S. 530, 534 (Consolidated Edison), quoting Cohen
v. California (1971) 403 U.S. 15, 24.) Thus, the First Amendment "both
fully protects and implicitly encourages" public debate on " 'matters
of public concern.' " (Pacific Gas & Electric,
supra, 475 U.S. at p. 9 (plur. opn. of Powell, J.), quoting
Thornill
v. Alabama,
supra, 310 U.S. at p. 101.)
To ensure "uninhibited, robust, and wide-open" "debate
on public issues" (New York Times, supra, 376 U.S. at p. 270),
the United States Supreme Court has recognized that some false or misleading
speech must be tolerated. Although "[u]ntruthful speech, commercial
or otherwise, has never been protected for its own sake" (Va.
Consumer Council, supra, 425 U.S. at p. 771), "[t]he First Amendment
requires that we protect some falsehood in order to protect speech
that matters" (Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. (1974) 418 U.S. 323,
341 (Gertz)). The "erroneous statement is inevitable in free debate,
and . . . it must be protected if the freedoms of expression are to
have the 'breathing space' that they 'need to survive' . . . ." (New
York Times, supra, 376 U.S. at pp. 271-272, quoting N.A.A.C.P. v. Button
(1963) 371 U.S. 415, 433.) Because "a rule that would impose strict
liability on a" speaker "for false factual assertions" in
a matter of public concern "would have an undoubted 'chilling'
effect" on speech "that does have constitutional value" (Hustler
Magazine v. Falwell (1988) 485 U.S. 46, 52), "only those false
statements made with the high degree of awareness of their probable
falsity demanded by New York Times may be the subject of either civil
or criminal sanctions" (Garrison v. Louisiana, supra,
379 U.S. at p. 74).
The majority contends its limited-purpose test for commercial
speech does not violate these principles because false
or misleading commercial
speech may be prohibited "entirely." (Maj. opn., ante, at
p. 954.) This logic is, however, faulty, because it erroneously assumes
that false or misleading commercial speech as defined by the majority
can never be speech about a [27 Cal.4th 984] public issue. Under the
majority's test, the content of commercial speech is limited only to
representations regarding "business operations, products, or services." (Maj.
opn., ante, at p. 961.) But business operations, products,
or services may be public issues. For example, a corporation's
business
operations
may be the subject of public debate in the media. These
operations may even be a political issue as organizations,
such as state,
local, or student governments, propose and pass resolutions
condemning certain
business practices. Under these circumstances, the corporation's
business operations undoubtedly become a matter of public
concern, and speech
about these operations merits the full protection of
the First Amendment. (See Thornhill v. Alabama, supra,
310
U.S. at p.
102.) Indeed, the
United States Supreme Court has long recognized that
speech on a public issue may be inseparable from speech
promoting
the speaker's
business
operations, products or services. (See Thomas v. Collins,
supra, 323 U.S. at pp. 535-536 [recognizing that a union
representative
could
not discuss the benefits of unionism without hawking
the union's services].)
The majority, however, creates an overbroad test that, taken to its
logical conclusion, renders all corporate speech commercial speech.
As defined, the test makes any public representation of fact by a speaker
engaged in commerce about that speaker's products made for the purpose
of promoting that speaker's products commercial speech. (See maj. opn.,
ante, at pp. 960-964.) A corporation's product, however, includes the
corporation itself. Corporations are regularly bought and sold, and
corporations market not only their products and services but also themselves.
Indeed, business goodwill is an important asset of every corporation
and contributes significantly to the sale value of the corporation.
Because all corporate speech about a public issue reflects on the corporate
image and therefore affects the corporation's business goodwill and
sale value, the majority's test makes all such speech commercial notwithstanding
the majority's assertions to the contrary. (See maj. opn., ante, at
pp. 965-967.)
In so doing, the majority violates a basic principle
of First Amendment law. (Consolidated Edison, supra,
447 U.S.
at p.
535 [restrictions
on the means by which a corporation "may participate in the public
debate" "strike[] at the heart of the freedom to speak"].)
By subjecting all corporate speech about business operations, products
and services to the strict liability provisions of sections 17204 and
17535, the majority's limited-purpose test unconstitutionally chills
a corporation's ability to participate in the debate over matters of
public concern. (See Garrison v. Louisiana, supra, 379 U.S. at p. 74.)
The chilling effect is exacerbated by the breadth of sections 17204
and 17535, which [27 Cal.4th 985] "prohibit 'not only advertising
which is false, but also advertising which[,] although true, is either
actually misleading or which has a capacity, likelihood or tendency
to deceive or confuse the public.' " (Maj. opn., ante, at p. 951,
italics added, quoting Leoni v. State Bar (1985) 39 Cal.3d 609, 626
(Leoni).) This broad definition of actionable speech puts a corporation "at
the mercy of the varied understanding of [its] hearers and consequently
of whatever inference may be drawn as to [its] intent and meaning." (Thomas
v. Collins, supra, 323 U.S. at p. 535.) Because the corporation could
never be sure whether its truthful statements may deceive or confuse
the public and would likely incur significant burden and expense in
litigating the issue, "[m]uch valuable information which a corporation
might be able to provide would remain unpublished . . . ." (Bellotti,
supra, 435 U.S. at p. 785, fn. 21.) As the United States
Supreme Court has consistently held, such a result violates
the First
Amendment. (Ibid.)
Finally, in singling out speakers engaged in commerce
and restricting their ability to participate in the public
debate, the majority
unconstitutionally favors certain speakers over others.
Corporations "have the right
to be free from government restrictions that abridge [their] own rights
in order to 'enhance the relative voice' of [their] opponents." (Pacific
Gas & Electric, supra, 475 U.S. at p. 14 (plur. opn. of Powell,
J.), quoting Buckley v. Valeo (1976) 424 U.S. 1, 49 & fn. 55.)
The First Amendment does not permit favoritism toward certain speakers "based
on the identity of the interests that [the speaker] may represent." (Bellotti,
supra, 435 U.S. at p. 784.) Indeed, "self-government suffers when
those in power suppress competing views on public issues 'from diverse
and antagonistic sources.' " (Id. at p. 777, fn.
12, quoting Associated Press v. United States (1945)
326 U.S.
1, 20.) The
majority, however,
does just that. Under the majority's test, only speakers
engaged in commerce are strictly liable for their false
or misleading
representations pursuant to sections 17204 and 17535.
Meanwhile, other speakers
who make the same representations may face no such liability,
regardless of the context of their statements. Neither
United States Supreme
Court
precedent nor our precedent countenances such favoritism
in doling out First Amendment rights.
III
The majority's limited-purpose test is not only problematic in light
of controlling high court precedent, the test appears to conflict with
the analysis used by other courts in analogous contexts. These conflicts
belie the majority's claim of doctrinal consistency and underscore
the illusory nature of its so-called solution to the commercial speech
quandary. [27 Cal.4th 986]
For example, the majority opinion conflicts with Gordon & Breach
Science Publishers v. AIP (S.D.N.Y. 1994) 859 F.Supp. 1521 (Gordon & Breach).
In Gordon & Breach, the defendant, a nonprofit publisher of scientific
journals, published scientific articles touting its journals as "both
less expensive and more scientifically important than those of for-profit
publishers such as" the plaintiff. (Id. at p. 1525.) The defendant,
as part of an advertising campaign designed to promote its journals,
touted and defended the conclusions of these articles by, among other
things, issuing press releases and writing letters to the editor responding
to attacks on these articles. (Id. at pp. 1526-1527.) In light of these
promotional activities, the plaintiff sued the defendant for false
advertising under the Lanham Trademark Act (15 U.S.C. § 1125(a))
and New York law.
In determining whether the defendant's advertising campaign
constituted commercial speech, the district court identified
the following
dilemma: how to characterize "speech which, from one perspective, presents
the aspect of protected, noncommercial speech addressing a significant
public issue, but which, from another perspective, appears primarily
to be speech 'proposing a commercial transaction.' " (Gordon & Breach,
supra, 859 F.Supp. at p. 1539.) After analyzing the relevant United
States Supreme Court precedent, the court concluded that the articles,
press releases and letters to the editor constituted noncommercial
speech fully protected by the First Amendment. (See id. at pp. 1543-1544.)
fn. 2 According to the court, this speech fell "too close to core
First Amendment values to be considered 'commercial advertising or
promotion' under the Lanham Act." (Id. at p. 1544.)
Application of the majority's test would, however, result
in a different outcome. The defendant was engaged in
commerce; it sold
journals.
The intended audience was undoubtedly potential customers.
The articles, press releases and letters contained representations
of fact about
the defendant's products--its journals. Thus, they contain
the
three elements of commercial speech identified by the
majority. The majority
would therefore classify this speech as commercial speech
even
though it constitutes "fully protected commentary on an issue of public
concern." (Gordon & Breach, supra, 859 F.Supp.
at p. 1544.)
Similarly, the majority's test creates a conflict with
Oxycal Laboratories, Inc. v. Jeffers (S.D.Cal. 1995)
909 F.Supp.
719. In Oxycal, the
defendants published a book that denigrated the plaintiffs'
products while promoting
the defendants' products. The defendants allegedly promoted
the book in an [27 Cal.4th 987] effort to boost the sales
of their
own products.
The plaintiffs sued, alleging false advertising. (See
id. at pp. 720-721.) Finding this case easy, the court
concluded
that
the
book was noncommercial
speech because there were "sufficient noncommercial motivations" notwithstanding
the commercial motivations. (Id. at pp. 724-725.) To the extent the
book contained commercial elements promoting the defendants' products,
these commercial elements were "intertwined" with
and secondary to the noncommercial elements. (Id. at
p. 725.)
Once again, the majority's test would yield a contrary result. The
defendants were engaged in commerce, and the intended audience for
the book was potential consumers. The book contained representations
of fact about the defendants' products, and the defendants undoubtedly
made these representations for the purpose of promoting their products.
Thus, under the majority's test, the book was commercial speech, and
the defendants would have been strictly liable for any false or misleading
statements about their products in the book.
Although we are not bound by these decisions, they are
instructive and highlight the deficiencies in the majority's
limited-purpose
test for commercial speech. In divining a new test for
commercial speech,
the majority finds a deceptively simple answer to a complicated
question. Unfortunately, the answer is flawed. By failing
to recognize that
a speaker's business operations, products, or services
may be matters of public concern, the majority ignores
controlling
principles
of First
Amendment law. As a result, the majority erroneously
draws a bright
line when "a broader and more nuanced inquiry" is required.
(Gordon & Breach, supra, 859 F.Supp. at p. 1537;
see also id. at p. 1540, fn. 7.)
IV
Of course, my rejection of the majority's limited-purpose test does
not resolve the central issue in this case: What level of protection
should be accorded to Nike's speech under the First Amendment? To answer
this question, this court, as the majority correctly notes, must determine
whether Nike's speech is commercial or noncommercial speech. Following
the existing framework set up by the United States Supreme Court, I
would conclude that Nike's speech is more like noncommercial speech
than commercial speech because its commercial elements are inextricably
intertwined with its noncommercial elements. Thus, I would give Nike's
speech the full protection of the First Amendment.
When determining whether speech is commercial or noncommercial,
courts must "ensure that speech deserving of greater constitutional protection
is not inadvertently suppressed." (Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. at
p. 66, fn. 11.) [27 Cal.4th 988] In following this philosophy in cases
involving hybrid speech containing both commercial and noncommercial
elements, the United States Supreme Court has assessed the separability
of these elements to determine the proper level of protection. If the
commercial elements are separable from the noncommercial elements,
then the speech is commercial and receives lesser protection. Thus,
advertising that merely "links a product to a current public debate" is
still commercial speech notwithstanding its noncommercial elements.
(Central Hudson, supra, 447 U.S. at p. 563, fn. 5.) Where the speaker
may comment on a public issue without promoting its products or services,
the speech is also commercial, even if the speaker combines a commercial
message with a noncommercial message. (See Board of Trustees, State
Univ. of N. Y. v. Fox (1989) 492 U.S. 469, 474 (Fox) [speaker did not
have to combine its sales pitch for Tupperware with its home economics
lessons].) Indeed, "[a]dvertisers should not be permitted to immunize
false or misleading product information from government regulation
simply by including references to public issues." (Bolger,
at p. 68.)
The United States Supreme Court has, however, recognized
that commercial speech may be "inextricably intertwined" with noncommercial
speech in certain contexts. (Riley, supra, 487 U.S. at p. 796.) Where
regulation of the commercial component of certain speech would stifle
otherwise protected speech, "we cannot parcel out the speech,
applying one test to one phrase and another test to another phrase.
Such an endeavor would be both artificial and impractical." (Ibid.)
In such cases, courts must apply the "test for fully protected
expression" rather than the test for commercial
speech. fn. 3 (Ibid.)
Although the United States Supreme Court has mostly found
this intertwining of commercial and noncommercial speech
in the
charitable solicitation
context, fn. 4 it has also done so in a factual context
analogous to the one [27 Cal.4th 989] presented here.
In Thomas v.
Collins, supra,
323 U.S. 516, fn. 5 the United States Supreme Court held
that a speech made by a union representative promoting
the union's
services
and
inviting workers to join constituted noncommercial speech
fully protected by
the First Amendment. (Id. at pp. 536-537.) Although the
court acknowledged that the speech promoted the services
of the
union and sought to
solicit new members, it found that these commercial elements
were inextricably
intertwined with the noncommercial elements addressing
a public issue--unionism. (See id. at pp. 535-536.) "The feat would be incredible for a
national leader, addressing such a meeting, lauding unions and their
principles, urging adherence to union philosophy, not also and thereby
to suggest attachment to the union by becoming a member." (Id.
at p. 535.) Indeed, "whether words intended and designed to fall
short of invitation would miss that mark is a question both of intent
and of effect. No speaker, in such circumstances, safely could assume
that anything he might say upon the general subject would not be understood
by some as an invitation." (Ibid.)
Finding that the commercial elements of the union representative's
speech should be accorded the full protection of the
First Amendment, the court concluded that distinguishing
between
the speech's
commercial and noncommercial elements "offers no security for free discussion." (Thomas
v. Collins, supra, 323 U.S. at p. 535.) "In these conditions," making
such a distinction "blankets with uncertainty whatever may be
said. It compels the speaker to hedge and trim." (Ibid.) "When
legislation or its application can confine labor leaders on such occasions
to innocuous and abstract discussion of the virtues of trade unions
and so becloud even this with doubt, uncertainty and the risk of penalty,
freedom of speech for them will be at an end. A restriction so destructive
of the right of public discussion . . . is incompatible with the freedoms
secured by the First Amendment." (Id. at pp. 536-537.)
[27 Cal.4th 990]
This case presents a similar scenario because Nike's
overseas labor practices have become a public issue.
According to
the complaint,
Nike faced a sophisticated media campaign attacking its
overseas labor practices.
As a result, its labor practices were discussed on television
news programs and in numerous newspapers and magazines.
These discussions
have even entered the political arena as various governments,
government officials and organizations have proposed
and passed resolutions
condemning Nike's labor practices. fn. 6 Given these
facts, Nike's overseas labor
practices were undoubtedly a matter of public concern,
and its speech on this issue was therefore "entitled to special protection." (Connick
v. Myers, supra, 461 U.S. at p. 145.) Because Nike could
not comment on this public issue without discussing its
overseas labor practices,
the commercial elements of Nike's representations about
its labor practices were inextricably intertwined with
their
noncommercial
elements. (See
Riley, supra, 487 U.S. at p. 796.) As such, these representations
must be fully protected as noncommercial speech in the
factual context presented
here. (See Thomas v. Collins, supra, 323 U.S. at pp.
535-536.)
The majority's assertion that Nike's representations
about its overseas labor practices are distinct from
its comments
on "policy questions" is
simply wrong. (Maj. opn., ante, at pp. 965-966.) The majority contends
Nike can still comment on the policy issues implicated by its press
releases and letters because it can generally discuss "the degree
to which domestic companies should be responsible for working conditions
in factories located in other countries, or what standards domestic
companies ought to observe in such factories, or the merits and effects
of economic 'globalization' generally . . . ." (Maj.
opn, ante, at p. 966.) The majority, however, conveniently
forgets
that Nike's
overseas labor practices are the public issue. (See,
ante, [27 Cal.4th 991] at p. 990.) Thus, general statements
about
overseas
labor exploitation
and economic globalization do not provide Nike with a
meaningful way to participate in the public debate over
its overseas
labor practices. (See Thomas v. Collins, supra, 323 U.S.
at pp. 536-537.)
Even if the majority correctly characterizes the public
issues implicated by Nike's press releases and letters,
its assertion
is still wrong.
In light of the sophisticated media campaign directed
at Nike's overseas labor practices and the close association
between
Nike's labor practices
and the public debate over overseas labor exploitation
and economic globalization, Nike could not comment on
these
public
issues
without discussing its own labor practices. Indeed, Nike
could hardly condemn
exploitation of overseas workers and discuss the virtues
of economic globalization without implying that it helps
overseas
workers
and does not exploit them. By limiting Nike to "innocuous and abstract
discussion," the majority has effectively destroyed Nike's "right
of public discussion." (Thomas v. Collins, supra, 323 U.S. at
pp. 536-537.) Under these circumstances, Nike no longer "has the
full panoply of protections available to its direct comments on public
issues . . . ." (Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. at p. 68, fn. omitted.)
Accordingly, the factual representations in Nike's press releases and
letters are fully protected under current First Amendment jurisprudence.
(See Thomas v. Collins, at pp. 536-537; Gordon & Breach,
supra, 859 F.Supp. at p. 1544.)
Such a conclusion is consistent with the commercial speech
decisions of the United States Supreme Court. Most of
these decisions involve
core commercial speech that does "no more than propose a commercial
transaction." fn. 7 (Pittsburgh Press, supra, 413
U.S. at p. 385.) Because speech that just proposes a
commercial transaction,
by definition,
[27 Cal.4th 992] only promotes the sale of a product
or service
and
does not address a public issue, these decisions are
inapposite.
The United States Supreme Court decisions finding hybrid
speech containing both commercial and noncommercial elements
to be
commercial are also
distinguishable. In these cases, the court found that
the commercial elements of the speech were separable
from its
noncommercial
elements and were therefore unnecessary for conveying
the noncommercial message. (See Fox, supra, 492 U.S.
at p.
474 [sales pitch for
Tupperware
was
not an indispensable part of the noncommercial speech
about home economics]; Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary
Council
(1985)
471 U.S. 626, 637,
fn. 7 [client solicitations were separable from noncommercial
statements describing legal rights].) Because the commercial
message was merely
linked to--and not inextricably intertwined with--the
noncommercial message, the court concluded that restrictions
on the commercial
message would not stifle the speaker's ability to engage
in protected speech.
As explained above, this case is different. Nike's overseas
business operations have become the public issue, and
Nike cannot comment
on important public issues like overseas worker exploitation
and economic
globalization without implicating its own labor practices.
(See, ante, at pp. 990-992.) Thus, the commercial elements
of Nike's
press releases,
letters, and other documents were inextricably intertwined
with their noncommercial elements, and they must be fully
protected as noncommercial
speech. (See Riley, supra, 487 U.S. at p. 796; Thomas
v. Collins, supra, 323 U.S. at pp. 536-537; Gordon & Breach,
supra, 859 F.Supp. at p. 1544.)
Finally, Bolger, the primary case relied on by the majority,
is distinguishable. In Bolger, a contraceptive manufacturer
wished to mail, among other
things, informational pamphlets that discussed the problem
of venereal
disease and the benefits of condoms and referenced the
manufacturer. The United States Postal Service banned
the mailings, and
the manufacturer challenged the constitutionality of
the ban. (See
Bolger, supra,
463 U.S. at pp. 62-63.) In assessing the constitutionality
of the ban,
the United States Supreme Court concluded that the informational
[27 Cal.4th 993] pamphlets constituted commercial speech "notwithstanding
the fact that they contain discussions of important public issues." (Id.
at pp. 67-68, fn. omitted.) Unlike Nike's overseas business
operations, however, the products at issue in Bolger
had not become a public
issue. Moreover, in the factual context of Bolger, the
manufacturer could
have commented on the issues of venereal disease and
family planning through avenues other than promotional
mailings
and without referencing
its own products. By contrast, Nike has no other avenue
for defending its labor practices, given the breadth
of sections
17204 and
17535 (see maj. opn., ante, at pp. 950-951), and Nike
cannot comment
on the issues of labor exploitation and economic globalization
without
referencing
its own labor practices (see, ante, at pp. 990-992).
Given these differences, Bolger does not compel the majority's
conclusion.
Constrained by the United States Supreme Court's current formulation
of the commercial speech doctrine, I would therefore conclude that
Nike's press releases, letters, and other documents defending its overseas
labor practices are noncommercial speech. Based on this conclusion,
I would find the application of sections 17204 and 17535 to Nike's
speech unconstitutional. Accordingly, I would affirm the judgment of
the Court of Appeal.
V
The majority attempts to refute the application of the inextricably
intertwining doctrine by factually distinguishing Thomas
and Thornhill. The majority's proposed distinction, however,
exposes a major flaw
in its analysis. According to the majority, Thomas and
Thornhill do not control because they neither address "the validity of a law
prohibiting false or misleading speech" (maj. opn., ante, at p.
965) nor bar states from prohibiting "false and misleading factual
representations, made for purposes of maintaining and increasing sales
and profits, about the speaker's own products, services, or business
operations" (ibid.). The majority apparently finds this distinction
persuasive because it previously concluded that Nike's speech is only "commercial
speech for purposes of applying state laws designed to prevent false
advertising and other forms of [27 Cal.4th 994] commercial deception." (Id.
at p. 964.)
Although the logic is difficult to follow, the majority
apparently characterizes corporate speech as commercial
or noncommercial
based on whether the speech is false or misleading. Such
an outcome, however, betrays a fundamental misunderstanding
of
the issue
presented
in
this case. As the majority acknowledges, state laws may
only prohibit false
or misleading speech if that speech is commercial. Thus,
the critical question is whether the speech at issue
is commercial or noncommercial
speech. Whether the statutes at issue are "designed to prevent
false advertising and other forms of commercial deception" has
no bearing on this question. (Maj. opn., ante, at p.
964.) The majority's assertion that Nike's statements
are commercial
speech
because the
application of false advertising laws is at issue therefore
makes no sense. (See ibid.) Indeed, the majority begs
the question by making false or misleading corporate
speech
commercial speech
because
it
is
false or misleading.
VI
In today's world, the difference between commercial and noncommercial
speech is not black and white. Due to the growing politicization of
commercial matters and the increased sophistication of advertising
campaigns, the intersection between commercial and noncommercial speech
has become larger and larger. As this gray area expands, continued
adherence to the dichotomous, all-or-nothing approach developed by
the United States Supreme Court will eventually lead us down one of
two unappealing paths: either the voices of businesses in the public
debate will be effectively silenced, or businesses will be able to
dupe consumers with impunity.
Rather than continue down this path, I believe the high court must
reassess the commercial speech doctrine and develop a more nuanced
inquiry that accounts for the realities of today's commercial world.
Without abandoning the categories of commercial and noncommercial speech,
the court could develop an approach better suited to today's world
by recognizing that not all speech containing commercial elements should
be equal in the eyes of the First Amendment.
For example, the United States Supreme Court could develop
an intermediate category of protected speech where commercial
and
noncommercial
elements are closely intertwined. In light of the conflicting
constitutional principles at play, this intermediate
category could receive greater
protection than commercial speech but less protection
than noncommercial speech. Under such an approach, false
or
misleading speech that
falls
within the intermediate category could be actionable
so long as states do not impose liability without fault.
(Cf.
Gertz,
supra,
418 U.S.
at p. 347 ["so long as they do not impose liability without fault,
the States may define for themselves the appropriate standard of liability
for a publisher or broadcaster of defamatory falsehood injurious to
a private individual"].)
Alternatively, the court could abandon its blanket rule permitting
the proscription of all false or misleading commercial speech. Instead,
the court could devise a test for determining whether governmental
restrictions on false or misleading speech with commercial elements
survive constitutional scrutiny. In doing so, the court could develop
a more nuanced approach that [27 Cal.4th 995] maximizes the ability
of businesses to participate in the public debate without allowing
consumer fraud to run rampant.
Even if these suggestions are unworkable or problematic,
the practical realities of today's commercial world require
a new " 'accommodation
between [First Amendment] concern[s] and the limited state interest
present in the context of' " strict liability actions targeting
speech with inextricably intertwined commercial and noncommercial elements.
(Dun & Bradstreet, supra, 472 U.S. at p. 756 (plur. opn. of Powell,
J.), quoting Gertz, supra, 418 U.S. at p. 343.) The high court long
ago recognized that "[t]he diverse motives, means, and messages
of advertising may make speech 'commercial' in widely varying degrees." (Bigelow
v. Virginia, supra, 421 U.S. at p. 826.) Given the growing
intersection between advertising and noncommercial speech,
such as political,
literary, scientific and artistic expression, this observation
is equally cogent
where the commercial speech is false or misleading.
I realize the task is not easy. Indeed, Justice Scalia
has recently alluded to the intractability of the problem.
(See
44 Liquormart
v. Rhode Island, supra, 517 U.S. 484, 518 (conc. opn.
of Scalia, J.) ["I
do not believe we have before us the wherewithal to declare Central
Hudson wrong--or at least the wherewithal to say what ought to replace
it"].) Nonetheless, a new accommodation of the relevant
constitutional concerns is possible, and the United States
Supreme Court can and
should devise a more nuanced approach that guarantees
the ability of speakers
engaged in commerce to participate in the public debate
without giving these speakers free rein to lie and cheat.
For example, such an accommodation could permit states to bar all false
or misleading representations about the characteristics of a product
or service--i.e., the efficacy, quality, value, or safety of the product
or service--without justification even if these characteristics have
become a public issue. In such a situation, the governmental interest
in protecting consumers from fraud is especially strong because these
representations address the fundamental questions asked by every consumer
when he or she makes a buying decision: does the product or service
work well and reliably, is the product or service harmful and is the
product or service worth the cost? Moreover, these representations
are the traditional target of false advertising laws. Thus, the strong
governmental interest in this context trumps any First Amendment concerns
presented by a blanket prohibition on such false or misleading representations.
By contrast, the governmental interest in protecting against consumer
fraud is less strong if the representations are unrelated to the characteristics
[27 Cal.4th 996] of the product or service. In some situations involving
these representations, the First Amendment concerns may trump this
governmental interest. A blanket prohibition of false or misleading
representations in such a situation would be unconstitutional because
the prohibition may stifle the ability of businesses to comment on
public issues. Indeed, this case offers a prime example. Making Nike
strictly liable for any false or misleading representations about its
labor practices stifles Nike's ability to participate in a public debate
initiated by others. Accommodating the competing interests in this
context precludes the blanket prohibition favored by the majority.
Although strict liability is inappropriate, an actual malice standard
may be too high because these representations undoubtedly influence
some consumers in their buying decisions, and the government has a
strong interest in minimizing consumer deception. Thus, a well-crafted
test could give states the flexibility to define the standard of liability
for false or misleading misrepresentations in this context so long
as the standard is not strict liability. fn. 8 (Cf. Gertz, supra, 418
U.S. at p. 347.)
VII
The majority accuses me of searching for my own "magic formula
or incantation" because I urge a reevaluation of
the commercial speech doctrine. (Maj. opn, ante, at p.
969.)
To this charge,
I plead guilty. Unlike the majority who finds nothing
unsettling about doctrinal
incoherence, I readily acknowledge that some wizardry
may be necessary
if courts are to adapt the commercial speech doctrine
to the realities of today's commercial world. Unfortunately,
Merlin
and Gandalf
are busy, so the United States Supreme Court will have
to fill the gap.
Although I make these magical references in jest, my point is serious:
the commercial speech doctrine needs and deserves reconsideration and
this is as good a place as any to begin. I urge the high court to do
so here.
達N 1. Except as otherwise noted, unlabeled section references are
to the Business and Professions Code.
達N 1. I take no sides in this public debate. Who is right and who
is wrong is not for me, or the majority, to decide. It is for the public-fully
informed as the First Amendment guarantees-to judge. (Gertz v. Robert
Welch, Inc., supra, 418 U.S. at pp. 339-340.)
達N 2. While the majority correctly observes that in
this constitutional analysis, "the very first question is whether the speech that
the law regulates is entitled to First Amendment protection at all" (maj.
opn., ante, at p. 968), it conflates this question with the issue whether
commercial speech may be regulated, the latter a foregone conclusion.
(Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. at p. 65.) Advocating what it calls a "limited-purpose" definition
of commercial speech (maj. opn., ante, at pp. 960, 966), the majority
proposes that a company's factual statements about its products or
services are commercial and subject to regulation if these statements
are "false or misleading." (Id. at p. 968.) In other words,
the majority concludes "a law that prohibits only such unprotected
speech cannot violate constitutional free speech provisions." (Ibid.)
Whether a company's statements are allegedly false or misleading does
not determine the threshold question at issue in this case-whether
the speech is commercial or noncommercial. (See Central Hudson Gas & Elec.
v. Public Serv. Comm'n (1980) 447 U.S. 557, 566.)
達N 3. The phrase " 'does "no more than propose a commercial
transaction" ' " (Bolger, supra, 463 U.S. at p. 66) "must
be understood to reflect judgments about 'the character of the expressive
activity' at issue judgments that necessarily entail an assessment
of the nature and constitutional significance of the larger social
practice within which that activity is embedded. That is why commercial
speech cannot be transformed into public discourse merely by altering
its content to insert assertions about matters of public concern." (Post,
The Constitutional Status of Commercial Speech (2000)
48 U.C.L.A. L.Rev. 1, 18-19, fns. omitted.)
達N 4. Contrary to the majority's suggestion (maj. opn.,
ante, at p. 965), the fact that the high court decided
both Thornhill,
supra,
310
U.S. 88, and Thomas, supra, 323 U.S. 516, before its
seminal cases on commercial speech, does not make these
earlier
cases' affirmation
of fundamental principles on First Amendment protection
less pertinent. Indeed, the high court relied, in part,
on Thornhill,
supra, 310
U.S. at page 102, in Va. Pharmacy Bd., supra, 425 U.S.
at page 762, to conclude
that "[t]he interests of the contestants in a labor
dispute are primarily economic, but it has long been
settled that both
the employee
and the employer are protected by the First Amendment
when they express themselves on the merits of the dispute
in
order to influence
its
outcome."
達N 1. All further statutory references are to the Business and Professions
Code.
達N 2. The court did find that the defendant's distribution
of preprints of the articles to potential customers and
its repeated
dissemination
of the conclusions of these articles to potential customers
constituted commercial speech. (Gordon & Breach,
supra, 859 F.Supp. at p. 1544.)
達N 3. The majority's attempts to distinguish Riley are
not persuasive. First, "charitable solicitations" do "involve factual
representations about a product or service that is offered for sale" (maj.
opn., ante, at pp. 966-967), where, as in Riley, the charitable solicitations
are made by professional fundraisers who solicit contributions for
a fee (see Riley, supra, 487 U.S. at pp. 874-785). Second, Fox does
not preclude the application of Riley in this case. (See maj. opn.,
ante, at pp. 966-967.) It is "impossible for Nike to address" certain
public issues without addressing its own labor practices
(maj. opn., ante, at p. 967), because these practices
are the public
issue and
symbolize the current debate over overseas labor exploitation
and economic globalization (see, post, at pp. 990-992).
達N 4. (See, e.g., Riley, supra, 487 U.S. at p. 796; Secretary of State
of Md. v. J. H. Munson Co. (1984) 467 U.S. 947, 959-960; Village of
Schaumburg v. Citizens for Better Environ. (1980) 444 U.S. 620, 632;
see also Meyer v. Grant (1988) 486 U.S. 414, 422, fn. 5 [finding the
solicitation of signatures for a petition to be noncommercial speech].)
達N 5. The majority contends Thomas and Thornhill are
not relevant because "[t]he United States Supreme Court issued these decisions
three decades before it developed the modern commercial speech doctrine
in Bigelow v. Virginia [(1975)] 421 U.S. 809, and Va. [Consumer Council],
supra, 425 U.S. 748." (Maj. opn., ante, at p. 965.) The majority,
however, conveniently neglects to mention that both Bigelow and Va.
Consumer Council cite Thomas and Thornhill with approval. (See Va.
Consumer Council, supra, 425 U.S. at pp. 758-759 [citing Thomas as
a case where the court "has stressed that communications to which
First Amendment protection was given were not 'purely commercial' "];
id. at pp. 757, 762; Bigelow, supra, 421 U.S. at p. 816.)
Thus, the United States Supreme Court, in developing
the commercial
speech doctrine, did not intend to overrule or diminish
the relevance of
Thomas and
Thornhill. In any event, the binding effect of a high
court opinion does not diminish with age.
達N 6. (See, e.g., Cleeland, Market Savvy Students Give
Sweatshop Fight the College Try, L.A. Times (Apr. 22,
1999) p. C1 ["a half-dozen
universities have adopted stringent codes of conduct for manufacturers
of apparel that bear their logos; many more are reexamining their policies"];
Martinez, Student Protests Unlikely to Kill UA-Nike Deal, Ariz. Daily
Star (Jan. 25, 1998) p. 1B ["Hundreds of UA students have signed
a petition protesting the university's impending contract with Nike
because of alleged human rights abuses in the company's factories overseas"];
Stepping Up Nike Criticism, Newsday (Nov. 10, 1997) p. A22 ["More
than 50 lawmakers yesterday called on Nike Inc. to improve labor standards
in Third World factories and to employ more people in the United States"];
Stancill, Students to Keep Pressure on Nike, Raleigh News & Observer
(Nov. 8, 1997) p. B1 [students signing and circulating petitions against
Nike]; Jeffcott, Consumer Power Takes on Brand Names, Big Retailers
(Sept. 7, 1997) 21 Catholic New Times 14, 15 [as part of the global
movement to end sweatshops, various groups are pressuring "city
councils to adopt 'no sweat resolutions' " directed
at multinational companies like Nike]; Himelstein, Going
Beyond
City Limits?,
Business Week (July 7, 1997) p. 98 [at least 10 cities
have passed no-sweatshop
ordinances directed at multinational companies like Nike];
Klein, Just Doing It Lands Nike in Ethical Hot Water,
Toronto Star (Feb.
24, 1997)
p. A19 [city council passes resolution banning the use
of child-made Nike soccer balls].)
達N 7. (See, e.g., Lorillard Tobacco Co. v. Reilly (2001)
533 U.S. 525, 536 [oral, written, graphic, or pictorial
advertisements for
smokeless tobacco and cigars]; Greater New Orleans Broadcasting,
supra, 527 U.S.
at p. 176 [radio broadcasts of promotional ads for casino
gambling];
44 Liquormart, Inc. v. Rhode Island, supra, 517 U.S.
at pp. 492-493 (plur. opn. of Steven, J.) [ads referencing
the price
of alcohol
products]; Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co. (1995) 514 U.S.
476,
481 [parties conceded
that labels on alcohol products listing alcohol content
was commercial speech]; Ibanez v. Florida Dept. of Business
and
Professional
Regulation, Bd. of Accountancy (1994) 512 U.S. 136, 138
[ads and promotional
communications listing professional affiliations of attorney];
United States v. Edge
Broadcasting Co. (1993) 509 U.S. 418, 421 [radio broadcasts
advertising lotteries]; Edenfield v. Fane, supra, 507
U.S. at pp. 763-764
[in-person solicitations for business by certified public
accountants]; Discovery
Network, supra, 507 U.S. at pp. 416, 424 [parties conceded
that magazines were commercial speech]; Posadas de Puerto
Rico Assoc.
v. Tourism
Co. (1986) 478 U.S. 328, 330 [casino ads]; In re R.M.J.
(1982) 455 U.S.
191, 196-197 [print ads and professional announcement
cards]; Central Hudson, supra, 447 U.S. at p. 562, fn.
5 [ads "clearly intended
to promote sales"]; Friedman v. Rogers (1979) 440
U.S. 1, 11 [trade name]; Ohralik, supra, 436 U.S. at
p. 454 [in-person
solicitation
of
business by lawyer]; Bates, supra, 433 U.S. at p. 354
[ads containing
pricing information]; Va. Consumer Council, supra, 425
U.S. at pp. 760-761 [ads containing drug prices]; Pittsburgh
Press
Co.
v. Human
Relations Comm'n (1973) 413 U.S. 376, 379 [job ads].)
達N 8. States may, however, adopt a strict liability standard for false
and misleading representations unrelated to the characteristics of
a product or service where the representations are not inextricably
tied to a public issue.