Practical Issues for TAs and Instructors
Mark Gonnerman
The true test of intelligence is not how much we know how to do, but how we behave when we don't know what to do.--John Holt, How Children Fail
While preparing to meet my first class as a teaching fellow in
East Asian Studies at Harvard in 1985, I visited several professors I
admire, told them of my new responsibilities and sought their
sagacious advice. My inquiries brought me up against the curious fact
that many university teachers are reluctant to talk about teaching,
even though they spend much of their professional time in the
classroom. While some professors entered into animated conversation
with me--"I find that I get nervous about meeting my classes even
after twenty-five years. Why do you suppose that is?"--a more common
response was along the lines of "Well, Mark, teaching is very
idiosyncratic. Either you have it within you to do it well or you
don't. Not very much can be said on this matter. Good luck."
It's true. Some people are more adept at teaching than others, and
temperament may be a distinguishing element here. New teachers spend
a lot of time searching for that particular style of communication
that will instruct and motivate others. But more can be said on this
matter than just this. To view teaching as utterly idiosyncratic is
to miss the fact that, like any art or craft, it entails a
recognizable set of attitudes and skills that can be learned and used
so that teachers and students might better express their own
voices.
In this essay I will introduce some practical, common sense
perspectives on teaching by commenting on three overlapping areas of
interest to beginning TAs. First, I will provide some specific items
to consider as you plan your first section meeting. First impressions
count in the classroom, and it is important to get off to a good
start. Second, I will introduce ideas for section leading and give
you some things to consider as you prepare to meet your students from
week to week. Finally, I will offer some thoughts on the nature of
your authority as a teacher. Questions surrounding authority are
often at the root of anxieties we bring to first (and subsequent)
class sessions.
I. Preparing for the First Section Meeting
While most teaching assistants are not in on syllabus planning, preparation for a course begins with attention to the syllabus and questions like What are the purposes of this course? Are assignments clear and reasonable? What are the aims of written work? Are materials on the syllabus good for discussion in sections? Will materials for the course be in the bookstore on time? What is expected from the professor and the TAs? How much autonomy will TAs have? Discuss these questions with the professor and other TAs far in advance of the first day of class. Make this one of many discussions you will have about the course. Ongoing conversation about the aims and effects of the course will likely influence the construction of future syllabi (yours and the professor's).
Early preparation also concerns the physical arrangement of the
classroom. Is the room an appropriate size? Do you have proper
furniture and equipment (chalk, markers, overhead projector, etc.)?
Will everyone seated around a table be able to see everyone else?
Where will you sit? Advance attention to details like these will free
up energy for interacting with students.
In the first class meeting it is good to enter into some kind of
substantive discussion related to the content of the course. In
addition, this meeting provides an opportunity to set the tone, lay
down some ground rules, begin the process of getting acquainted, and
generate interest among students. Students are very interested in
learning just how open and accessible you are, so the manner
in which you present yourself and items for discussion is of the
utmost importance.
I like to arrive early to the first class and write the following information on the board:
Once students are comfortably settled, I introduce myself with reference to the above information. You will have to decide how much more you want to say about yourself at this time. I usually talk about how I became interested in the subject matter and identify several aspects of the course that I'm particularly excited about. I also mention something I hope to learn more about as the quarter goes along.
I next emphasize that section meetings are for discussion. It is, therefore, important that students get to know each others' names and make an effort to get acquainted for the sake of the class. To get this process started--and it will take several class meetings before people begin to feel comfortable with each other--I hand out 4" X 5" index cards and ask students to record information like the following (noting that it is optional to do so):
The final item on this list will open up avenues of conversation
that go beyond the bounds of the course. These cards will prove
helpful as you start to put faces with names.
Before collecting these cards you may want to use them to help
students introduce themselves. I like to pair students up, have them
exchange cards, converse a few minutes and introduce their partner to
the group. Students won't remember many names at this point, but the
ice will be broken enough to move things along. At the beginning of
the next class you may have everyone state their name before
selecting someone to go around the room naming each and every person.
This exercise gets people to attend to learning names, especially if
you say you may ask somebody else to do this at the beginning of the
next meeting. In these early meetings you might also have students
make name cards which they set on the table.
Once introductions are taken care of, it is time to look more
closely at the syllabus and set ground rules for discussions and
written work. By reviewing the syllabus you let students know where
the course is going and how, in your mind, various topics fit
together. Students will learn better if they keep this overall
picture in mind. By setting ground rules that let students know your
expectations and policies concerning their work, you become
trustworthy as you put your cards out on the table. What, for
example, is your policy toward late written work? Do you expect
people in the section to arrive on time? What will you expect from
students who are making class presentations?
Think carefully about your expectations and policies, for you will
be bound by them as the course goes along. Deviations from stated
policies are often the cause of trouble; it is to everyone's
advantage if you are firm and remain consistent with the framework
set forth the first class. Reiteration and explication of these items
will probably be required at a later date, especially around the time
when the first written work comes due.
Every class period should be carefully planned in advance. There
is never enough time and you must set priorities. While introductions
and discussion of expectations and procedures are necessary, it is
important that a portion of the first class be devoted to
intellectual work. After all, the main purpose of discussion sections
is to examine texts and ideas in ways that promote the development of
intellectual virtues. Giving part of the hour to consideration of a
question or small portion of a text will help set an appropriate
tone.
Choosing a substantive issue for the first day can be difficult.
Time will be limited and you will want to find something that piques
curiosity and points to questions and concerns that will be important
throughout the course. In some classes reading for the first section
will already be assigned on the syllabus. In that case, I recommend
you select just one important paragraph from the assignment and work
with that. Have students read this paragraph in silence before asking
if anyone would like to summarize it (those who haven't already done
the reading are then included). Ask for additional summary statements
and have a student or two raise a question for the group to consider.
A discussion may take off from there.
If the selected passage is from a supposedly familiar text (i.e.,
something students may have encountered in a required freshman
seminar like CIV), you may wish to work through it line by line,
showing what close reading is about. Students will find things in the
familiar text they have not noticed before, and you can point out
that the kind of attentive reading and rereading just demonstrated
will enhance their appreciation of assignments throughout the
term.
If you are not starting with something already assigned, you may
wish to demonstrate close reading with a text you select and bring
in. You may also begin with a relevant newspaper clipping, or start
by summarizing conflicting interpretations of a salient idea in work
for the coming week. Whatever you do, remember that students will
learn a good deal about the way you plan to facilitate section
discussions. This first session, then, provides a great opportunity
for setting an appropriate tone, demonstrating your approach to
discussion leading, drawing attention to important skills and
creatively introducing course material. Don't worry if time runs out
before the discussion really gets off the ground. The rest of the
quarter lies ahead!
II. Leading Discussion Sections
In the course of your life as a student you have undergone an
"apprenticeship of observation." That is, you have observed a lot of
teaching over the years. Your experience as a student is one of your
best resources for preparing to teach. Which models will you emulate?
Which will you try to avoid? In this section I will note several
important characteristics that distinguish effective teachers. Good
teachers are imaginative, well-prepared, flexible, and available.
A. Imagination
After many years of schooling, teachers and students have come to
expect certain norms in classroom life. Sadly, many students will
assume that life inside the classroom isn't going to be very
interesting or relevant to life outside. This poses a challenge to
your imagination. Are there ways you can upset expectations and
improve classroom culture so students might change their ideas about
the value of classroom time? Can you imagine ways of keeping students
off guard so that they remain attentive and eager to exercise their
skills? What happens if, for example, you try to introduce ideas in a
text through music or pictures?
In most classrooms--even those intended for discussion--lines of
instruction run separately from the teacher to each individual
student. While this may be convenient for instructors, this dyadic
dynamic inhibits the creation of an atmosphere where students will
learn to work together. Are there ways of facilitating greater
communication among students so that interaction extends beyond the
class hour and makes classroom time less discrete?
I once set things up so that students in my section were writing
to and for each other. It has always seemed strange to me that
students rarely read each others' papers. Why should communication in
writing go only from student to teacher? In an effort to upset this
norm, I arranged things so that each week a student would write a
short essay on a very broad question relevant throughout the course.
All students wrote on the same question--something like What is
history? What is scripture? What is the good life? Why should one
study religions? The first draft of this paper was read by two
students who commented on it in writing. The author took these
comments into account and composed a final version. The final draft,
attached to the first draft and peer comments, was then turned in to
me.
This experiment had many good effects. The papers generated
ongoing conversation about the one, broad question students shared.
Writing kept conversation about the question topic going, people
remained interested in how others would approach the question and
references to ideas in these papers came up in class discussions. I
learned that students are very interested in what their peers think
and appreciate the opportunity to express their ideas through the
more controlled vehicle of writing. Finally, students learned to
value rewriting and the process of collaborative learning, one of the
purposes of the discussion section format.[3]
One of the main aims of discussion sections is to help students
learn how to learn through participation in the life of a group. You
may want to be very explicit about the skills that are necessary for
this and discuss these skills in your class. You can't assume that
students understand the reasons why lectures and sections are
organized as they routinely are. Use your imagination to
upset the routine--thereby drawing attention to it--and find ways of
facilitating interaction among students who are capable of learning
from each other. (See Mark Unno's "Pedagogical Tools and Strategies"
for additional ideas.)
B. Preparation
If you expect students to be serious and prepared, you must be
well-prepared too. You will teach much by example. Have you been to
the week's lectures? Have you worked through course materials with
points for discussion in mind? That is, have you identified essential
tensions and questions in the materials assigned for the day? Have
you clarified your goals for the section meeting? What would you like
students to be thinking about when they walk out the door? How does
what you are doing in section relate to the course as a whole?
It is good to begin class meetings by helping students focus on
the hour that lies ahead. Students often arrive in section with a
variety of things on their minds (sleep, food, sex, the last class,
the next class, the weekend, etc.). I help them prepare mentally for
class by taking a few minutes to review salient features of the last
meeting and give an overview of plans for the present hour. This
draws everyone together, creates narrative continuity and turns
attention to matters at hand.
Students will forgive most everything except the offense of being
obviously under prepared. Being well-organized and helping students
focus on immediate tasks demonstrates that you care about the course
and value class time.
C. Flexibility
It is possible to be over prepared. In this event you may be so
set on covering your agenda that you leave little room for student
input and spontaneous "teachable moments." The atmosphere in a
discussion section should be one of give-and-take. If you are too
organized, there will not be enough room for spontaneity: creative
energies will wane and the class will lose its conversational tone.
If one is not organized enough, discussions may be unfocused and
difficult to summarize and assess.
While it is important to arrive with an agenda in mind, you should
be flexible enough to bring extemporaneous questions and ideas into
your plan. Since good discussions have a life of their own,
unexpected insights may take the class in surprising and exciting
directions. You will have to assess whether unanticipated detours are
productive or distracting.
If you begin the class by spelling out an agenda, the session can
end (as it should) with a summary of what has transpired. If items on
your agenda were not spoken to, you have a way of measuring what was
accomplished by relating it to your original plan. Sensing just how
much preparation is necessary and knowing when and how to get things
back on track when unproductive digressions appear is an art you will
learn over time.
D. Availability
Student surveys repeatedly indicate that a TA's availability is a
primary concern. While you cannot be available twenty-four hours a
day (and some students might expect this), you have an obligation to
be available when and where you say you will be. Set office hours and
stick to them.
Office hours often provide some of the best teaching time. Quieter
students will be more forthcoming (not everyone is comfortable
expressing themselves in the larger group), and you will have a
chance to become better acquainted with your students as you meet to
discuss particular ideas and projects.
It is also important to be available at the end of each class
hour. Be careful not to schedule anything that will prevent your
interaction with students at this time. Some students will use this
time to ask questions they weren't able to bring to the group. They
may also want to push the preceding discussion further. This is also
a common time for discussing assignments and arranging meetings
during office hours.
III. Your Authority as a TA
At institutions such as Brown or Stanford you are teaching in a
lively, multicultural environment. As a teacher, you represent
academic culture. That you are a TA indicates you have learned to be
at home in the academic world, and that you understand its rituals,
procedures, languages, politics, and resources. The fact that there
may be things about academic culture that you do not like is itself
an indication of your growing familiarity with it.
When you walk into your first class meeting, students--however
suspicious they appear--are going to view you as someone with a
tremendous amount of authority. In large part, this is because you
represent success in a culture they want to participate in and know.
Since questions concerning the nature and exercise of authority are
at the root of many of the anxieties TAs have, I want to briefly
grapple with that vexing problem here.
I think your main task as a teacher is to help students articulate
and explore genuine questions--questions that somehow connect
students' lives to the subject matter at hand. The skill you most
need to develop is that of guiding others through the process
of working toward meaningful answers. Your authority as a TA is based
on your proven ability to identify and explore serious questions. The
best, most immediate, resource you have for developing this skill is
your own experience as a learner: When confronted by a genuine
question, how do you proceed?
TAs are usually better off when they claim authority on the basis
of their ability to learn. Good teaching, then, is not a matter of
presenting yourself as a walking Encyclopaedia Britannica,
(though information is fundamental to the teacher's task). The good,
most authoritative teacher is one who is able to engage others in a
process of discovery. This process of discovery and the excitement it
generates is what makes life in the university worthwhile.
I mentioned that one of the best resources you have for becoming
articulate about the processes and joys of scholarship is your own
experience as a learner: When confronted by a genuine question, how
do you proceed? One of the best ways to prepare for teaching a course
is to reflect upon this question so that, through your words and
actions, you may communicate those energies, insights, and resources
that have carried you along.
When stepping into the teaching role, it takes courage to trust in
your own experience, use your own voice, and really be yourself. It
takes courage not to try and be somebody else--probably the most
common mistake beginning teachers make. In honestly expressing
yourself and drawing on your own experiences and inner resources, you
will be able to claim and enjoy authority as a college teacher.
Conclusion
In the epigraph to this essay, John Holt suggests that
intelligence is best indicated by how one behaves in a new situation.
While college teaching isn't entirely new to you (remember your
apprenticeship of observation), the transition you are making from
being a student to being a teacher sets you in a situation that
brings new responsibilities and problems. If it seems that my advice
is common sense, that's good. Becoming a teacher can be difficult,
and in difficult situations it is not uncommon to throw common sense
right out the window.
It will take some time to become comfortable in this transition,
and patience is required. It helps to remember that the teachers you
most admire and plan to emulate have become good at what they do
because they have been working on it for a number of years. They have
experimented, measured student responses, reflected on their aims,
talked to colleagues and fine tuned their particular approaches. Now
you can begin to do the same.
Mark Unno
In the course of my work as a teaching assistant and instructor, I
have had the opportunity to try out a variety of tools and
strategies, and I would like to share some of them. Many will already
be familiar with them as they have had occasion to encounter them in
other situations or as students. Furthermore, they are not
necessarily specific to religious studies and can generally be used
in any humanities course. Nevertheless, I thought it might be helpful
to review some of them.
Weekly Short Assignments
I have found it useful to assign one- to two-page response papers
on a weekly or bi-weekly basis. I ask students to reflect on each
week's readings and to bring in a few well-thought-out questions or a
brief analysis of an idea or passage that they found particularly
insightful, difficult to understand, or otherwise thought-provoking.
I collect these short assignments at the end of each section and
return them the following week with my comments. Making comments on
these short assignments and returning them regularly assures the
students that the teacher cares about their work and maintains
two-way communication. I do not grade them, but they are required,
and together with their participation in the discussion sections
accounts for approximately one-tenth of the students' course
grades.
These assignments fulfill several functions. They help students to
reflect on the readings and provide the teacher with a means to get a
sense of their overall development. This in turn enables the teacher
to understand students' longer papers better and to make more
meaningful comments on them. They provide a springboard for
discussion; the short assignment makes certain that students have
something prepared for discussion, and shy students tend to be more
confident in speaking up if they have something written prepared. It
is also easier for me to call on students when I know they have
something ready. If the discussion bogs down, I can always call on
someone to present what they have prepared.
I have generally found that the short paper fulfills these
functions well. Even when I was TAing for a course that satisfied a
double distribution requirement and was graded pass/no-credit,
students consistently handed in these assignments, made insightful
points, and used them to engage in high-level discussions.
Student Presentations
Each week, I also ask students to pair up to make ten-minute
presentations on the readings. I suggest that one student present
some analysis or problem and that the other respond, but I leave the
format fairly open. Depending on the number of students in the
section, each member of a discussion section usually ends up doing
these presentations one to three times. Most of us have had
experiences with this in graduate seminars, and I have found that it
works quite well for discussion sections in lecture courses.
I usually begin the section with these presentations. This allows
students to take control of the discussion and present ideas that
they are most interested in. Usually students are able to carry on a
focused discussion based on the initial presentation for fifteen to
twenty-five minutes, and I only intervene when necessary, that is, to
correct misinformation or to refocus a discussion that has gone too
far off on a tangent.
When the discussion initiated by these presentations begins to
wind down, I either pose further questions that I would like to have
the students consider or make my own presentation as a supplement to
or clarification of the readings and lectures.
I have found that discussion sections serve two main purposes: to
clarify and elaborate upon course material that could not be covered
adequately during lectures and to help students develop their ability
to discuss and reflect on the material intelligently. Beginning
discussion sections with student presentations first and introducing
one's own material later on is one way to balance these elements.
Student Debates
I usually have students engage in debates two or three times a
semester. Of course, debate is a normal part of any discussion
section, but here I am referring to a more formal situation in which
students are asked to represent a particular position. I first
learned of this as a teaching intern for Hester Gelber's Philosophy
of Religion (RS42) at Stanford University and have used this
often.
I prepare a passage of paragraph-length which describes a scenario
involving problems relevant to the course material and pass it out to
the students at section. I have the students divide up into groups of
four to six and have each group represent one position. For example,
I might have different groups represent the position taken by Hume,
Kant, and Kierkegaard on the question of the existence of God. Each
group elects a spokesperson, and after ten to fifteen minutes of
discussion, the spokespeople engage in debate with each other in an
attempt to establish their own position and to critique the
others.
This has been a useful format for several reasons. It helps
students to develop discussion skills, to learn what it means to
represent a particular position, and to take on perspectives that
might not reflect their own personal convictions. As Steve Wilson has
noted,[5] this is a particularly
helpful format for certain students and even whole sections that tend
to be reserved, as it is often easier for such students to play a
role rather than give voice to their own position.
The debate format is especially helpful in courses with a
philosophical dimension, since effective argumentation is essential
to philosophical discourse. It can contribute significantly to the
study of nearly all subjects to the extent that critical analysis and
argumentation constitute a part of most academic work. It is also a
nice change of pace to insert debates during the course of a
quarter.
Grades
Grades are, it seems, a necessary evil of higher education. There
is an unavoidably subjective element in grading papers, and it is
difficult to be consistent. As a TA I found various standards applied
by different professors, and I tried first of all to be consistent
with the individual instructor's own standards. It is important for
students in different sections of the same course to have the same
standards, and one of the easiest ways to achieve this is to consult
with the instructor and to come to some kind of consensus regarding
standards that are consistent across sections. If one has strong
disagreements with the instructor in this regard, they can and should
be voiced.
One advantage of being aware of the instructor's standards is that, when students have grievances concerning grades, the TA can appeal to the instructor as a referee. Eventually, however, TAs must be weaned from reliance on the instructor's authority and be willing to take sole responsibility for grading. I have my own genearal criteria for grading which I use as an instructor, and these are explained in the sample "Paper Writing Guidelines" which have been included in this volume. I make adjustments in these criteria for different courses as necessary.
Students at institutions such as Brown and Stanford are
intelligent and motivated, and it is fairly unusual to give a grade
below a B-. There are, however, often enough cases in which students'
work is less than adequate, and lower grades given accordingly.
Whenever I do I ask the student to speak with me briefly, either
after section or during office hours. I do this for several reasons:
1) to make sure that students understand why they received the grade
they did, 2) to suggest ways of improvement, and 3) to encourage
students and highlight the positive points of their papers. Time and
again I have been surprised to see how students improve in their
writing over the course of a quarter.
There were several instances in which the students' writing was so
poor that I was not certain whether they could complete the course
satisfactorily, but after making some suggestions and encouraging
them, virtually all of these students reached a surprisingly high
level of proficiency by the end of the course. I recall one case,
however, where a student performed quite well on the rewrite allowed
for first papers but failed to reach her potential later on. It was a
case where she simply had other priorities.
In another interesting case, a student received a low grade, and
when I explained why, he told me that he knew he had not done a very
good job but did not want to do a rewrite. He also did not contribute
much to the discussions and seemed rather disinterested. In such
cases I sometimes try to involve the student by calling on him or her
and making various suggestions. But in this case, something told me
that I should just let him be. He was in a small section of highly
capable and motivated students. He remained silent through most of
the quarter but became visibly more interested as he was infected by
the enthusiasm of the others. He gradually took a deeper interest in
the course, and his writing naturally improved. Sometimes less is
more, as this case seemed to illustrate.
Peer Review
Another tool I began using this past year is the peer review. Mark
Gonnerman had mentioned this to me, but I decided to use it for the
first time in two seminars that I taught this past year, using my own
format.[6] Students were
required to hand in drafts two weeks before the final due date and
exchange papers with a partner. Once the peer reviewers made comments
on the draft, they were required to hand in the drafts with comments
to me, and I in turn made comments on the comments. This process
served to refine student writing, empowered students to benefit from
one another's work, enhanced the collaborative character of their
study, and brought more focus to bear on the quality of writing and
thinking rather than on quantity. In both classes the the effect on
the quality of writing was positive across the board, and students'
response to the peer review was equally strong.
Working with Other TAs and Instructors
I have learned a great deal from other TAs as well as from my own
teachers and colleagues, and I have found it helpful to work with
them in a variety of ways. Especially in my early experiences, I
found it just as helpful to consult with more experienced TAs as with
the instructor. This has included everything from procedural matters
to the presentation of specific ideas.
Sometimes I had TAs from other sections serve as a guest TA for my
section. Students in the section were thus exposed to different
styles and approaches to the same material, and their learning was
enriched through broadening the scope of their experience. At times I
asked other TAs to consult with students in my section when they had
particular difficulty understanding the material or working on a
paper. Other TAs may be more knowledgeable in certain areas, or they
may be able to provide an angle that I had overlooked. Teaching is a
highly individual affair, and much depends upon the chemistry between
teacher and student. While there may be consistently good teachers,
no one is good with every student.
One helpful tool for gauging students' experiences in section is
the mid-quarter evaluation. I have most often used anonymous
evaluation forms for this purpose. Most departments have standard
forms that can be used, but I have usually formulated my own, for two
reasons: 1) Standardized forms usually have a ranking scale for
different areas of pedagogy as well as specific questions; I have
found that students tend to focus on the ranking scale at the expense
of providing detailed comments, and the latter are often more helpful
for making adjustments midway through a course. 2) I also make minor
changes in the form depending on the course.
Handouts
Various types of handouts have proven beneficial. I have already
touched on the Paper Writing Guidelines which have been included in
this volume. I would like to mention just three other types that I
have used: 1) supplementary bibliographies, 2) glossaries of names
and terms, and 3) diagrams. Supplementary bibliographies with
brief descriptions of the works listed can be helpful, because
bibliographical information for works cited frequently by the TA but
not listed in the course syllabus can be included. Glossaries
are useful for making sure students know the spelling for certain
terms, providing brief definitions of terms students are expected to
know, and generally highlighting key concepts and names.
Diagrams provide a means to organize one's thoughts, as
schematic presentations of key concepts provide a framework in which
various ideas can be placed. In this sense, diagrams, like
theoretical generalizations, are limited but useful. Here is a case
where a picture is not worth a thousand words but meaningful
nonetheless.
Conclusion
The tools and strategies described above are just a few of the
ways in which I have tried to make the learning experience for
students as meaningful as possible. Each teacher will develop her own
strategies as she builds on her experience, and I look forward to
learning more from what others have to offer as I continue to develop
my own repertoire.
Mark Unno
The idea for "Paper Writing Guidelines" began with my work as a
teaching assistant as I started to assign and grade papers. At first
I explained orally what I expected and required regarding the
procedures, mechanics, content, and overall evaluation of papers.
However, I began to recognize that students sometimes did not
remember everything, and I was having to spend a great deal of time
explaining these matters during section as well as writing the same
comments on papers repeatedly.
I decided to hand out a written set of guidelines for papers to
lessen my work in this regard. In addition, the Guidelines proved a
helpful reference for questions and grievances that arose. Students
were clear about what was expected, and I was accountable for my own
position.
The Guidelines seem to be helpful, as students have responded
positively, both in terms of their feedback regarding the Guidelines
and the quality of their written work. Two of the most important
skills that are taught at the undergraduate level are how to think
and write well. The two are distinct but closely interrelated, and it
has been my experience that a basic foundation in clear and organized
writing often aids in the development of critical thinking skills. In
humanities courses, the written paper is the only tangible evidence
of the students' work, and it is our responsibility as teachers to
see to it that they are given the necessary tools to excel.
This requires a grasp of basic procedure and mechanics. They are
like the tools used by a carpenter or the utensils of a chef. Without
a basic knowledge of these instruments, the carpenter cannot complete
a project, the chef cannot cook an adequate meal, and the college
student does not have the necessary framework to express her ideas
effectively. Beyond these basics, the college or university paper
usually represents a genre that is more complex than anything
students have attempted before and incorporates elements that are new
to their thinking and writing. I will not go into each area in detail
here; the sample which follows is fairly self-explanatory in this
regard.
Students may sometimes become preoccupied with the details of the
Guidelines, and their writing may become cramped in an effort to
satisfy the instructor. In order to counterbalance this tendency, a
brief essay on academic writing as a creative process, "Writing: The
Bridge between Consciousness and Unconsciousness", has also been
included after the Guidelines.
The Guidelines presented below are in turn meant to serve as a
guideline for your own thinking about these matters, and I merely
hope that they will stimulate reflection.
(This is a dated version; for a more current sample, click here)
Mark Unno
Please follow these guidelines when writing your papers.
1. Deadlines
Submit your papers by the deadlines stated in the syllabus. If for
some reason you cannot hand in a paper on time, contact me by the day
before the due date. In all reasonable cases I will give you an
extension, but if you don't let me know, there will be a grade
deducted for each day it comes in late.
2. Mechanics
Mechanics are important. They are the basic tools that make the
paper possible.
a) Descriptive Title. As simple as this is, some people do
forget.
b) Page numbers. In case the pages come loose, I will be able to
read your paper.
c) Consistent citations. You may use either footnotes, endnotes,
or intra-textual parenthetical notes. However, do not mix forms of
citation. There are some exceptions to this rule. Some examples of
standard citation formats follow:
Footnotes and endnotes
Books: Etty Hillesum, An Interrupted Life (New York:
Washington Square Press, 1985), 42-44.
Article in an anthology: Hideki Yukawa, "The Happy Fish," in
Experimental Essays on Chuang-tzu, ed. by Victor Mair, 85-100
(Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1983).
Journal article: Philip J. Ivanhoe, "A Happy Symmetry: Xunzi's
Ethical Thought," Journal of the American Academy of Religion
49:2 (Summer 1991), 309-310.
Intra-textual note
(Ivanhoe 1991:309-310).
Bibliography
Yukawa, Hideki. "The Happy Fish." In Experimental Essays on
Chuang-tzu, ed. by Victor Mair, 85-100. Honolulu: University of
Hawaii Press, 1983.
For a more detailed explanation of standard formats, consult:
Kate Turabian's A Manual for Writers of Term Papers, Theses,
and Dissertations, 5th ed., rev. by Bonnie Birtwistle (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1987).
If you do use intra-textual references, be sure to provide a full
bibliography of cited works at the end of your paper.
d) Use block quotations for citations four lines or longer. When
using block quotations, do not use quotation marks at the beginning
and end of the block.
e) Check your spelling. There should be few errors in this
regard.
3. Style
There are a few stylistic matters to be aware of.
a) Avoid using too many conjunctions and qualifiers, such as
"however," "then," and "given that." Except in a few cases, the
reader will know how one sentence relates to the next without the use
of these terms, and the resulting paper will be easier to read.
b) Use natural English. There is no need to fill your paper with
technical vocabulary or difficult terms. If you do use them, they
will have a greater effect when you write for the most part in clear,
straightforward English.
c) Tenses. Be consistent in your use of past and present tense. If
you are writing a thought paper (ideas, philosophy), it is accepted
practice to put everything in the present tense. For example, you may
write, "The Buddha says, . . . ." or "The Tibetan master Milarepa
behaves in unconventional ways."
If you are writing a research paper dealing with historical
issues, you should put scholarly assertions in the present tense ("I
think," "Gregory Schopen states") and historical facts in the past
("Sakyamuni delivered a sermon," "Devadatta turned traitor"). In any
case, be consistent.
d) Documentation. Whenever you make generalizations or assertions,
document your claims with citations, either from the lectures or
readings. If you make a statement that seems controversial and you
don't cite a reference, then I will not know where your ideas came
from. You cannot be too careful on this point
e) Subheadings. They are not required, but it can be helpful to
insert subheadings as you go along. They let the reader know that new
topics are being addressed.
f) Gender. It is now widely considered that the exclusive use of
male pronouns to refer to both sexes is unacceptable. There are a
number of strategies that can be used to negotiate this matter. You
may use i) male and female pronouns alternately, ii) neutral pronouns
such as "one" and "they"; however, avoid mixing these two pronouns in
the same sentence, iii) both (When a person finds him or herself in
this situation . . .), or iv) "s/he". If you have any questions about
this, please see me.
4. Drafts
You are not required to submit drafts, but I will be happy to look
at them for you. It is the surest way to improve your performance,
and it will help both your thinking and your writing. At the same
time, I won't have the time to look at a draft at 10:00 p.m. the
night before a paper is due. Please give me at least three days
before the due date to look over a draft.
5. Types of Papers
There are generally two types of papers, thought papers and
research papers. There are commonly elements of both present, but
papers largely fall into one of the two categories.
a) Thought papers may make use of materials beyond the required
reading but need not do so. Rather, the focus is on careful study,
analysis, and elaboration of ideas presented within a limited
context, such as a single article. It is often helpful to focus on
one idea, passage, or paragraph and consider the ramifications
thereof.
b) Research papers deal with a careful study of objective evidence
available to support and refute arguments. You do not need to go to
outside material, but it is often helpful to obtain supporting
evidence to back up your assertions.
For the purposes of this course, you may choose either type, but
the emphasis will be on the former. You may write on one of the
suggested topics, or you may choose your own topic; in the latter
case the instructor's approval is required.
6. Grading Criteria
Although grading is an imprecise art, it is possible to attain a
considerable degree of consistency. I look for the following when
reading papers:
a) Writing. If you write clearly and grammatically, you will think
clearly and in an organized fashion. If you think clearly, this will
be reflected in your writing.
b) Accuracy. Have you represented the relevant ideas fairly?
c) Sophistication. Have you taken into account various facets of a
problem or idea? You can be accurate at a general level ("The Buddha
was a seeker of truth."), or you can be accurate at a sophisticated
level ("The Buddha was a seeker of truth who formulated his
understanding in terms of the four noble truths.").
d) Breadth of knowledge. Have you covered the main ideas relevant
to your topic?
e) Depth of analysis. How deeply have you delved into the topic?
Have you uncovered problems that might not be apparent at first
glance? How carefully have possible objections been taken into
account?
f) Engagement and effort. How hard have you tried to tackle the
topic? Even if the paper might not seem so great at first glance, it
will be apparent if you have made an honest attempt to understand
what you are studying.
g) Creativity. Do you have a flair for expressing yourself? Are
there unexpected insights and a sense of adventure?
Although there are no hard and fast rules, if you cover criteria
a) through d) and execute them well, you should get a B. Provided you
have gone that far, you can add further dimensions to your paper. If
you have any questions about comments I have made on your paper or
your grade, please come and see me. It is important for me to know of
any doubts or problems.
Rewrites will be allowed for the first paper only.
7. In Conclusion
If you study these guidelines, it will make the learning
experience more pleasurable and rewarding for both you and me. At the
same time, this represents nothing more than what it says,
"guidelines." They are meant to help you polish a skill, academic
writing, that you are developing as you progress in your studies.
Don't get so hung up about them to the extent that you feel your
creative processes hindered. If anything, they should provide just
enough of a framework to express your creative and analytical skills.
The accompanying essay addresses the creative aspect of paper
writing.
Megumi and Mark Unno
I like writing. When I am totally absorbed in writing, many ideas
which have never occurred to me before can pop up in my mind, or once
confused and fragmentary information and thought can be spontaneously
organized and become clear. It is one of the most satisfactory
moments for me.
Yet, I often struggle for long periods trying to organize ideas in
front of the cruel white paper. This is especially true when I am
trying to be systematic and logical, beginning with an outline. Since
anything unclear or vague is eliminated in the process of making an
outline, the paper turns out to be organized, clear, and compact, but
I rarely have a sense of satisfaction.
What is the difference between a paper which emerges spontaneously
and one that begins with a concern for logical consistency? I have
been wondering how I can bridge the gap between these two types of
writing and the attitudes they represent. I have found some clues to
these problems in three articles written by Donald Murray, Peter
Elbow, and William Stafford.[9]
What they emphasize in common is the process; writing is not the
description of a result; in fact, writing itself can create the
result. This means that we should not worry too much about how the
last draft will turn out, or how we can organize all of our ideas
before we begin. According to Murray, what we need for writing is
enough information and a clear purpose: logic or order can appear
later in the process. Elbow even denies the need for coherence in the
initial stages of producing writing. He suggests "freewriting," which
activates the writing process by getting rid of any concern about
correction. Also, Stafford remarks that the most important things for
his writing are receptivity and a willingness to give up high
standards. For all of these writers, logic and organization, which
has restricted me in certain ways, are secondary at the initial stage
of production. It is true that logical rigor is important, but we can
worry about that as much as we like after everything has been written
down that we want to say.
What is important in writing is, as the three writers agree, the
productivity of writing. According to Murray, for example, writing is
the process of "making something that was not there before, finding
significance where others find confusion and bringing order to
chaos."[10] By writing you can
find new things, which may be a new thought, a new feeling, a new
idea, or even a new self which you would never have found without
writing.
In order to promote this kind of productivity, Murray, Elbow, and
Stafford agree on the importance of opening our minds. Murray points
out that writing gives us an opportunity to capture, at the conscious
level, unconscious feelings and ideas we had not noticed or had
forgotten. Elbow says freewriting is a method to make our
consciousness empty so that we can pick out something unconscious
from deep within our hearts. Stafford remarks that the power letting
him write is not a conscious device but his "own weak, wandering,
diffident impulses" and his "confident reliance" upon these
impulses.[11]
Writing might be compared to a breeze blowing towards the small
window between consciousness and unconsciousness. The window is
usually closed because consciousness is too strong to let the window
open, and one ends up living in only half of the house, that is, the
entire world of one's existence. But when writing occurs with the
mind open, a breeze opens the window and one can encounter other
aspects of the self, or even another self and become more fully
integrated: The wonder of the writing process may even be the act of
another self.
When I try to stick to the rules of logic from the outset, my
consciousness prevents the window from opening to the other world. My
writing then becomes a mere product of my pre-existing consciousness
rather than the activity of my whole self. Repeated experience and
practice of freewriting has helped me to open my mind. I can worry
about logic and organization after my creative impulses have found
expression on paper.
Creating
a Teaching
Portfolio[12]
Mark Gonnerman
*What is a teaching portfolio? It's a collection of materials
documenting your strengths and accomplishments as a teacher. Peter
Seldin, author of The Teaching Portfolio (Anker, 1991), says "The
portfolio is to teaching what lists of publications, grants and
honors are to research and scholarship."
*What should my portfolio include? There is no one formula for
preparing a teaching portfolio. Each portfolio reflects the
capabilities and responsibilities of different, individual teachers.
However, portfolios typically include a brief table of contents, a
personal statement, supporting material from others, and evidence of
effective teaching. Your portfolio is not an exhaustive compilation
of everything that reflects your teaching performance. It's a
selective, thoughtful collation making the best case for your
effectiveness as a teacher.
*Personal Statement. Personal statements are generally 4-6 pages
long and may include the following items: 1) a reflective statement
of your pedagogical interests, strategies, and objectives; 2) a
summary of your past and present teaching responsibilities; 3) a
description of steps taken to evaluate and improve your teaching,
including changes resulting from attending teaching workshops, being
videotaped, or meeting with a Center for Teaching and Learning (CTL)
teaching consultant; 4) an explanation of appended supporting
materials such as syllabi, exams, handouts and other evidence of
effective teaching.
*Supporting Material from Others. You may include: 1) statements
from professors with whom you have worked as a teaching assistant; 2)
statements from professors, other teaching assistants, and colleagues
who have observed you in the classroom; 3) student statements and
evaluations of your teaching (forms are available at CTL); 4)
documentation of teaching/development activity with CTL staff,
including written results of student small group evaluations and
video consultations.
*Evidence of Effective Teaching. You may wish to submit: 1) copies
of exemplary student essays; 2) student work you have graded showing
excellent, average, and poor work along with an explanation of your
grading and evaluation strategies; 3) an audio or videotape of you
lecturing or leading a discussion section. (Videotapes made by CTL
can be purchased at cost.)
*Collaborate. Teaching portfolios are best prepared in
consultation with others. As you put your portfolio together, seek
the advice of your academic advisor, other TAs, and members of the
CTL consulting staff. One great benefit of assembling a teaching
portfolio is that it helps you become more articulate about your
teaching strategies as you review and reflect on your work, consult
with others, and clarify your pedagogical aims.
*Summary. There is no one way of compiling a teaching portfolio.
The above suggestions provide general guidelines. Use them to
assemble a portfolio demonstrating your particular interests and
accomplishments. And remember, your portfolio is not set in stone.
The contents will change as your teaching experience and insight
grow.
Historical
Context and Diverse Understandings
Shaping
the Curriculum: The Emergence of Religious Studies[13]
Sumner B. Twiss
I have been asked to address the curricular ramifications of the
emergence and development of the field of religious studies-with
particular reference to Brown University. I am happy to do so, but
must make it clear that when it comes to history I am an amateur (my
areas are comparative religious ethics and philosophy of religion,
not history). So what I'll be discussing are some of my impressions
about the topic, informed by some rather skimpy materials in
university and departmental archives and guided by three brief but
insightful historical sketches of the field and its curricula-one
published by John Wilson (Princeton University) in 1970, another by
Thomas Benson (University of Maryland-Baltimore) in 1987, and
(especially) a third published by Frank Reynolds (University of
Chicago) in 1990.
Let me start with a brief "external" history of the department
that I found in our departmental files and which, I think, reflects
the development of both field and curricula within older "private"
nonsectarian colleges and universities more generally. The department
had its origins in the 19th century when the study of classical
languages and literatures ruled the day-including Greek, Latin,
Hebrew, Biblical and other philosophical and theological texts. In
1891 a professor of semitic languages and oriental history (William
Jewett) was appointed to the faculty, and in 1897 a Department of
Biblical Literature and History was established. In 1935, with the
appointments of Robert Casey and Joachim Wach (the first a specialist
in what we now call "early Christianity", and the second, an
omnicompetent historian and sociologist of religion with an interest
in both Western and non-Western religious traditions), the
department's name was changed to the Department of Biblical
Literature and the History of Religions. In 1953, following a
Corporation Committee Report on the status of religion within the
university, the department's name was changed once again to reflect
developments in the field: the Department of Religious Studies. These
nominal changes mark important developments in the field as well as
significant evolution in the curriculum, and so I now turn from this
brief capsule view to discuss what I perceive as important issues of
subject-matter, method, and curricular thinking lying behind these
name changes.
Underlying these changes is a gradual evolution of the department
and field through four phases, each with a relatively distinctive
conception of the study of religion and a relatively distinctive
curricular paradigm. Adopting and refining Reynolds' three-fold
typology of Early Modern, Late Modern, and Post-Modern, I identify
the four phases as: Early Modern Theological (roughly 1800-1900),
Transitional Ethnocentric (roughly 1900-1950), Late Modern
Critical-Scientific (roughly 1950-1975), and Post Modern
Hermeneutical (roughly 1975-1991). This typology may over-simplify,
and the labels may not be entirely satisfactory, but they will have
to serve (e.g., one can discern sub-phases within and overlapping
between these four phases). Notice, by the way, that by my accounting
each successive phase is relatively shorter than the preceding one,
reflecting the intensity of methodological self-exploration and
understanding of the field. I now want to characterize each of these
phases in terms of what I perceive to be its corresponding conception
of the study of religion in general as well as a curriculum
appropriate for undergraduates-I leave graduate study to one side in
these formal remarks. Since I have been asked also to address general
socio-cultural and institution-specific factors that may bear on the
emergence and development of these phases, I'll do that too, but with
considerable unease about my competence to do so (here I will rely
heavily on Reynolds, Wilson, and Benson to help me out). When I state
intersubjectively verifiable facts that have some consensus, I'll so
indicate; when I interpret, I'll say so; when I speculate, I'll say
so (without apologizing each time).
The first phase-Early Modern Theological-needs to be understood in
the context of what Reynolds claims was the predominant educational
mission of most colleges in this period (late 18th to mid-late 19th
century). They were, he suggests, committed to preparing students for
taking up positions of intellectual and social leadership in what was
perceived to be a relatively homogenous society and culture-by
providing them with trained minds and restrained passions, both of
which were to be achieved by a strong grounding in classical
languages and literature. In this period, the study of religion in
American colleges was dominantly theological, aimed at the
understanding and apologetic defense of the Christian way of life. It
focused on the subject-matter of what the Christian scriptures say or
imply and how this content is played out in terms of a rationally
based theological worldview and morality. It employed the methods of
philologically oriented study of Christian Scriptures (New Testament,
Old Testament) combined with Enlightenment-oriented reasoning about
the nature and justification of the Christian religion and its
claims. Faculty undertaking these inquiries were professors of
divinity with (I speculate) college-seminary training in major
relevant primary languages, study of scripture, and theology.
This conception of the study of religion as theology is expressed
in a curriculum that has as its fundamental mission the initiation of
students into a reflective Christian way of life (what Wilson calls
"religious-moral nurture"). Courses appear focused on scriptural
study in the original languages as well as careful reading of major
English-language works in natural theology and natural law. In 1821,
for example, Brown's total curriculum was 20% theological, including
courses in the Greek New Testament, Paley's Moral Philosophy, Paley's
Natural Theology, Paley's Evidences of Christianity, Butler's Analogy
of Religion, Barlemagni's Natural Law. Pedagogy, then, appears to
involve (as expected) study of classical languages and literature as
well as study of theological texts with an eye to evidences and
arguments for the truth of Christianity.
The second phase-Transitional Ethnocentric-needs to be understood
in a socio-cultural context of what I speculate is a society becoming
increasingly aware of its heterogeneity-especially following World
War I and the waves of immigration that came shortly thereafter-a
society less insulated from other societies and cultures and a
society that is industrialized and becoming increasingly oriented to
science and technology. Reynolds claims that colleges and
universities at this time are beginning to conceive of their mission
as preparing students for technical leadership in a modern industrial
and scientific world and have decreased commitment to providing
religious-moral nurture. (Indeed, as early as 1891 at Brown, the
function of religious enculturation is split off from the curriculum
and assigned to agencies at the periphery of the
curriculum-chaplains, Y. M. C. A., voluntary Bible classes conducted
by the President, etc.). Reynolds further suggests that the colleges
and universities feel increasing pressure and need to devote greater
proportionate attention to the sciences and somewhat less
proportionate attention to the humanities. He also reminds us that
this period sees the gradual emergence of the psychological and
social sciences claiming to be a distinctive set of disciplines
essential for understanding human behavior and social institutions
and needing incorporation within the education of future leaders.
It is documentable that the conception of the study of religion in
this period shifts from the explicitly theological to the historical
understanding of Christianity (origins and development) in comparison
and contrast with other religious traditions. The aim is to
historicize the study of Christianity by employing tools of critical
history and literary analysis and by comparing its content with the
scriptures and historical development of other traditions, both East
and West. Its methods include philological tools, standard techniques
of historical inquiry, literary analysis, as well as some use of
concepts and models adopted from the social sciences. Faculty
undertaking these inquiries include both professors of biblical
literature and history and professors of the history of religions.
Most (I speculate) are trained at university-based divinity schools
or independent seminaries, some at theological faculties in foreign
(principally German) universities.
This conception of the field is played out in gradual changes
within college curricula. Brown is a forward-looking case example.
The curriculum now sees its mission in both research and teaching as
to connect the "study of the bible with the general history of
religions" (East and West) and to emphasize "the importance of
religion as a factor in general culture . . . an active and
measurable force in individual and social history" (Visiting
Committee Report, Department of Biblical Literature and History of
Religions, 1938, quoted in departmental file history). With regard to
students, this presumably means their initiation into a critical
understanding of the history and literature of their perceived
primary tradition (Christianity) conceived as being enhanced both by
comparison with other world religious traditions and by exposure to
(e.g.) sociology of religion. Courses include a dominant "core" in
biblical literature and history (Old Testament, New Testament,
biblical themes and topics such as "Social Teachings of the Prophets
and Jesus"), but this "core" is increasingly surrounded by courses in
ancient civilizations (taught with the Classics department),
contemporary religion (the development of modern forms of Judaism and
Christianity), religions of the Orient, primitive religion, and
sociology of religion (taught with the Sociology department).
Pedagogy appears less focused on language-training-this period
documents the emergence of the study of biblical literature in
translation (beginning around 1910), which is (I interpret) a
reflection of the demise of the classical education associated with
the Early Modern Theological curricular paradigm. It is to be
emphasized that the theological orientation of that earlier phase no
longer holds sway, though this is not to say that the curriculum is
not still appreciably ethnocentric in its orientation to Christianity
as the religious tradition of primary focus and interest. The
biblical "core" is a "core", and the comparison of Christianity with
other traditions is in service of understanding Christianity better
(or so I interpret).
The third phase-Late Modern Critical-Scientific-marks a
"watershed" (as our departmental file history puts it) in the
development of the study of religion at Brown as well as in American
higher education more generally. Here, I speculate, we have a society
that, after World War II, has emerged as a dominant force in the
modern world-decisively involved in the affairs of other societies
and cultures, conceiving of itself as self-consciously secular,
scientific-technological, pluralistic, and egalitarian. Reynolds
suggests in so many words that college and universities now conceive
of their mission as to prepare an increasingly diverse student body
for leadership through critical training in the natural and social
sciences (primarily) and the humanities (secondarily). But these
generalities aside, it is clear that, following upon the breadth of
advances of the Transitional phase in the study of religion, a
relatively "hospitable environment" (in Wilson's words) exists for
further development of the field. This is, in fact, the period where
the academic/scholarly study of religion emerges in its full
flower.
The 1953 Brown Corporation Report in "Religion within the
University" expresses this complete emergence quite well. It clearly
distinguishes the work of the department from that of the chaplaincy,
and it specifies that the mission of the department is now to pursue
a scholarly understanding of "the nature and role of religion," with
an emphasis on "a historical approach," though intended to work in
"the philosophy of religion, its sociological implication, and the
areas of conflict with scientific thought," covering the study of
Christianity, Judaism, and other religions. The aim of the field,
then, is conceived to be the historical-scientific-philosophical
study of religions, self-consciously employing multi-disciplinary
tools and methods in the effort to understand, interpret, and explain
features of the world's religious traditions. The ethnocentric bias
of the past is broken. The limitation on methods of critical inquiry
is ended. And we can see in the emphasis on combining historical,
philosophical, and sociological approaches an underlying commitment
to the ideal of detached objectivity and value-neutral inquiry-in
strong and self-conscious contrast with work done in the earlier
phases. "Critical" and "multidisciplinary" and even "scientific" are
the watchwords here. Over this period, we see faculty coming to be
increasingly trained by graduate programs in religious studies with
self-conscious commitment to these aims and methods; as
seminary-trained scholars retire, they are replaced by people fully
trained in the academic study of religion.
Needless to say, this large development in the study of religion
results in concomitant changes within the curriculum. No longer is
its aim explicitly theological or mutedly ethnocentric. Its mission
now is to initiate students into the critical study of the world's
religious traditions so that they might appreciate and understand in
an historically deep and theoretically sophisticated way the nature
and role of religion in human life. Courses involve sophisticated
periodization and contextual-ization of the history of traditions,
East and West. They involve exposure to alternative critical methods
of inquiry as well as interpretive and explanatory theories of
religion (e.g., psychoanalytic, phenomenological, social-functional,
cultural-symbolic). And, generally over time, they increasingly
include a broadening of the "texts" studied with reference to
religions-not only basic scriptural canons and major intellectual
figures but also ethnographic data, aesthetic forms, etc. Rather
surprisingly, perhaps, given this openness to alternative critical
methods and the sorts of texts studied, the pedagogy of these courses
remains somewhat "traditional" in the sense of employing the standard
lecture/discussion section format, mid-term and final exams, a final
term paper. This may be due to the enormity of the task taken on by
these courses of trying to teach students both a large amount of
information as well as a variety of approaches-resulting in the felt
need to teach somewhat didactically (this is my interpretation).
The fourth phase (thus far)-Post Modern Hermeneutical-like the
other phases, has a distinctive socio-cultural context. Reynolds
suggests that this context involves the vivid and self-conscious
awareness of pluralization within American society-as represented,
for example, by the increasing size and "voice" of minority
groups-and a vivid and self-conscious awareness of an interdependent
global world order-as reflected, for example, in global concerns
about the natural environment, the legacy of the nuclear arms race,
the extent of starvation and suffering throughout the world.
Furthermore, one cannot help but notice an important intellectual
shift away from the hitherto dominant image of detached, objective,
and value-neutral inquiry. Suggests Reynolds, gone is the
Enlightenment myth of monolithic objective reason able to produce
algorithms for "proper" science, "proper" morality, "proper" social
change, etc. In its place is a rather more humble sense of the
reaches of context-dependent rationality and the historical and
social location of all human endeavors. And it should not go
unnoticed that colleges and universities must take account of a
student body shaped by such self-conscious plurialization, global
sensitivity, and historical and social awareness. I suspect that many
colleges and universities have adjusted their mission accordingly and
now conceive of themselves not only as preparing such students to be
scientifically and rhetorically competent but also as responsible for
educating them in such a way that they may be able to grapple
critically and creatively with social and global problems of
considerable political, historical, and moral complexity. Brown would
be no exception.
My perception is that the academic study of religion is
significantly affected by this socio-cultural context-in both aim and
method. One can discern, I believe, a clear interest in approaching
religious traditions as complex organic systems embodying forms of
life and thought that have their own rational integrity different
from but just as "authentic" as the rationality of research programs
and disciplines concerned with the study of religion. So the aim of
religious studies becomes less of a hegemonic theoretic effort to
explain (objectively) the religious Other and more of an attempt of
one "equal" to understand and appreciate another "equal". Though the
critical methods of inquiry that have been employed are certainly
still used (with appropriate refinement and expansion, e.g., feminist
critique), nonetheless they are now used with a somewhat different
manner and tone: to set up an interdisciplinary and intercultural
dialogue with the worldviews of the traditions being studied. A more
self-consciously humble dialogue or hermeneutical conversation is
established to probe not only the traditions under study but also the
assumptions, norms, and values of the disciplines doing the study.
Ethnocentrism is left firmly behind-not just in the sense of not
presuming the priority of a certain religious tradition but also in
the sense that the scholar must be ever alert to more subtle
ethnocentric (and gender) biases built into disciplinary approaches
and methods. I, for example, can no longer do comparative religious
ethics in the way that I did in the late 1970's and early 1980's:
developing an analytical framework based on western moral
philosophy's typology of normative moral theories (e.g., varieties of
deontology, consequentialism, etc.) and then blithely imposing this
as a sortal device on non-western religious-moral traditions,
thinking that I can therewith understand these traditions in their
subtlety and nuance (often involving ideals of character and virtue
and norms of rationality very different from my own and the framework
that I employ). If I use this framework at all-as perhaps a means of
starting up a conversation with traditions I am interested in
studying-I must now allow these traditions to critique (as it were)
my framework and all of the assumptions about self, society, and
human nature that may underlie it.
Now such changes as these cannot but help to be reflected in
curricular development in religious studies. The goal now becomes to
initiate students into a critical understanding of and dialogue with
religious traditions conceived as complex forms of life and thought
with their own integrity and rationality, different from but prima
facie equal to our own. Teaching and learning are more focused on
using methods of inquiry in a radically self-critical way to foster
deeper understanding of the problems posed by trying to make sense of
other cultures and religious traditions. Questions arise: What does
the world look like from the Other's point of view? How can we know
that it looks the way we think-as revealed by a certain method-given
the possible tension between the way we construe the world and the
way that the Other construes the world-after all, are not all ways of
construal historically, socially, and culturally conditioned? As
might be expected, this sort of teaching and learning requires some
change in pedagogy-away from "traditional" didactics and toward more
interactive learning designed to foster awareness of the significance
of interdisciplinary dialogue and comparative inquiry as
hermeneutical conversation between disciplines and traditions. More
discussion classes, more frequent short papers focused on problems of
critical interpretation, and a willingness to engage normative issues
(aesthetic, moral, political) that may surface in interpretation and
conversation. And so in addition to methodology and theory of
religion, sophisticated periodized history of religions
(Christianity, Islam, Judaism, Hinduism, Buddhism, Taoism,
Confucianism, Israelite, ancient Greek & Roman, etc.), our
department now has such courses as Comparative Religious Thought:
Judaic & Christian; Parables and Paradoxes: The Limits of
Language & Redescriptions of the Self; Religious Ecstasy &
Performance in the Hindu Tradition; Secular & Sacred Readings:
Paul, Pascal, Kierkegaard, & Kafka; Religion & the Good
Society: Sex, Children, & Gender; Calvin's Institutes: Rereading
the West's Master Narrative; War & Religion in the Near East;
Freudian Ego and Id from the Perspective of Western Religious
Thought; Sacrifice & Sacred Violence in Ancient Religions; The
Compassionate Way: Confucian & Buddhist Ethics (in dialogue with
western understandings of altruism); Status of Women in Early
Christianity; Women in Religion; etc.
By this time in my discussion, I hope that you are gaining a
clearer sense of not only the history of curricular development in
religious studies but also the nature of religious studies as a field
of academic inquiry. I think that two issues remain to be addressed.
First, how exactly does this field now understand itself? That is, is
it a distinctive discipline, or what? Second, why exactly are there
departments of religious studies? That is, how does one explain the
existence of free-standing departments and disciplines? The answer to
the first question has been provocatively addressed by Benson. He
suggests quite straightforwardly that religious studies is not one
discipline per se-representing one distinctive mode of cognitive
inquiry governed by a single set of questions, goals, norms, and a
community of scholarly consensus-but rather a "community of
disciplines" brought together to focus on a common subject-matter in
all of its myriad richness and complexity. He observes, quite
correctly I think, that simply having a common interest in the study
of religion is insufficient in itself to justify viewing this study
as a single unified discipline (though there have been unsuccessful
attempts in the past to project a "science of religions"). As Benson
points out, there is no shortage of multidisciplinary scholarly
groups in the academic world, brought together by general themes or
shared subject-matter (often, I might add, in the form of
extradepartmental or interdepartmental centers and programs-this
university is notable for its past encouragement of such efforts). So
why exactly a department of religious studies, given this
understanding of religious studies as a community of disciplines
gathered around a common subject-matter?
John Wilson, I believe, provides the beginnings of an answer to
this second question. He suggests that two significant types of
factors lie behind the trend in American higher education to form
departments of religion rather than to permit the "diffusion of the
study of religion" throughout other already established disciplinary
departments in colleges and universities. The first type of factor is
practical: colleges and universities may perceive administrative and
organizational advantages in establishing separate and free-standing
departments of religion (e.g., I speculate, avoidance of interminable
turf-battles over allocation of FTEs to the study of religion,
seeking development monies for a new department, etc.).[14]
While this type of factor may constitute a necessary condition for
departmental establishment, it seems insufficient by itself. The
second sort of consideration advanced by Wilson is more
"theoretical": the need, as Wilson puts it, for the co-residence of
scholars involved in the study of religion, so that they and their
field might benefit from the cross-fertilization of ideas that comes
from sustained interaction in doing research and developing
curricula. Taken together, these two sorts of
factors-administrative-practical and scholarly-theoretical-may be
sufficient to explain why we have departments of religion, but I (for
one) am not entirely convinced. I think that other factors may have
been at work here; for example (and this is speculation based on the
Brown case): the professional eminence of scholars in the study of
religion during what I have identified as the transitional phase
(Millar Burrows, Robert Casey, and Joachim Wach were major
international figures in the study of religion who left Brown for
more prestigious institutions, e.g., Yale and Chicago); the need for
the university, the field, and the transitional phase department to
distinguish in a decisive way the academic study of religion from the
past university role of religious-moral nurture; the fact that
religions constitute a significant type of cultural force and
dimension of human experience and behavior roughly coordinate with
art, politics, economics, etc.; the rise of identifiable professional
organizations and journals dedicated entirely to the academic study
of religion; and so the list could continue. I suggest, then, that
the confluence of myriad factors and forces virtually overdetermine
the decision to found departments of religious studies. In my
opinion, that decision has borne considerable fruit. There is no
question in my mind that the academic study of religion would be
considerably worse off if departments with stabilized and interacting
faculty, graduate programs, and undergraduate programs had not been
formed. American higher education is not alone in this view
apparently, for following upon the American experience, there have
been comparable developments in other countries as well.
By way of conclusion in the form of a postscript, I might mention
that I shared a draft of my remarks with some of my colleagues in the
department in order to solicit their critical response to my
historical vision of religious studies at Brown. I am happy to report
that all found it instructive, thought-provoking, and largely
accurate-a somewhat heartening response-but some thought that I may
have overplayed or downplayed certain points, and these are worth
sharing with you. First, some suggested that I may overestimate the
extent to which 19th century students studied the Bible in the
original languages. Perhaps, but all I can say is that the catalogues
of the university indicate rather clearly that both the New Testament
and the Old Testament (the Christian version of the Bible) were read
in the original languages (though greater emphasis was placed on the
New Testament) and that a wide variety of language courses were
taught at various levels. Second, some suggested that I ought to
emphasize that graduate training in the history of religion in the
post-modern period incorporates both philosophical-methodological
sophistication and the detailed mastery of religious texts and that
this training helps to account for the hermeneutical character of the
post-modern undergraduate curriculum. This observation is, I think,
clearly true, and I accept the clarification with gratitude. Third,
at least one colleague thought that I ought to mention that the
post-modern curricular paradigm includes courses in "constructive
religious thought" (as distinguished from the doing of theology per
se)-that is, courses that explore how systems of religious thought
might (or indeed, ought to) respond to non-religiously based
understandings of human nature, society, and culture, with it being
understood that the inquiries in such courses are answerable to
canons of reflection and argument typically associated with the
university context as contrasted with canons of theological argument
as might be specified by particular religious institutions or
communities of faith. I am happy to accept this clarification as an
extension of my point about the re-emergence of normative inquiry in
the post-modern curriculum.
Bibliography
Catalogues of Brown College/University, 1820-1991
"Departmental History," Files of the Department of Religious
Studies.
Citing:
Visiting Committee Report, Department of Biblical Literature and
History of Religions, 1938
Report of the Special Committee of the Corporation on Religion
Within the University, 1953.
John F. Wilson, "Introduction: The Background and Present Context
of the Study of Religion in Colleges and Universities," in Paul
Ramsey & John Wilson (eds.), The Study of Religion in Colleges
and Universities (Princeton University Press, 1970), pp. 3-21. Thomas
L. Benson, "Religious Studies as an Academic Discipline" (sub-entry
of three-part article entitled "Study of Religion"), Encyclopedia of
Religion, 16 vols., Mircea Eliade, editor in chief (Macmillan,
1987).
Frank E. Reynolds, "Reconstructing Liberal Education: A Religious
Studies Perspective," in Frank E. Reynolds & Sheryl L. Burkhalter
(eds.), Beyond the Classics? Essays in Religious Studies and Liberal
Education (Scholars Press, 1990), pp. 3-18.
Related Useful References:
Ninian Smart, The Science of Religion and the Sociology of
Knowledge (Princeton University Press, 1973).
John F. Wilson & Thomas P. Slavens, Research Guide to
Religious Studies (American Library Association, 1982), esp. ch. 1
("The Study of Religion").
Jonathan Z. Smith, "Narratives into Problems: The College
Introductory Course and the Study of Religion," Journal of the
American Academy of Religion 56: 4 (Winter 1988): 727-739.
S. Nomanul Haq
Teaching living religions is tricky business, but teaching Islam
is trickier than most. The reasons, it seems to me, are obvious; but
let me offer a word of explanation.
Courses on living religions always draw a fair number of those
students who come from families traditionally belonging to that
specific faith which happens to be the subject matter of the course.
Let us call these students "believers"--but with one proviso: they
may not be so in the strict sense of the word; nor is it always the
case, so experience has taught us, that they consciously share their
parental religious identities at all. What motivates these students
to take college courses on their "own" religion is a phenomenon that
is both complex and fascinating, something that deserves a thorough
sociological study in its own right. But one thing is certain, and it
is that their motivation generally arises, at least partially, out of
some inner personal concern.
So to speak, the rhythm of the believers is different from that of
the rest in the class. There are things that touch them deeply, same
things which are treated with disinterest by others; many specific
religious terms, phrases, formulas, and anecdotes strike a familiar
chord in the listener who is a believer, while for the rest all this
is likely to serve a cognitive function, rather than an existential
one. Then, there are issues which in the history of religions have
been profoundly divisive; there are, for example, questions of
theological controversies, heresies, betrayals, persecutions,
bloodshed, and wars. Here the believer may have heard accounts that
are at variance with that of the teacher, and the believer may have
inclinations to be sympathetic with the "culprit" rather than the
"victim," and with the "heretic" rather than the "faithful"--thereby
tending to reverse the standard scholarly appellations.
It is very easy for the teacher to forget all this, and it is for
this reason that I say that teaching living religions is a tricky
issue. True, in the world of learning we have made an uncompromising
commitment to respect all faiths and creeds equally, to encourage
critical inquiry, and never to impose dogma, nor to indoctrinate. But
beyond the boundaries of our campuses lies a bigger world; in that
world many divisive religious issues are alive: here much
polarization does exist, and here religious battles are still being
fought. We cannot possibly view our students in isolation from this
bigger world. When they come to college, they inevitably bring with
them a heavy baggage of popular and private perceptions.
This baggage is heavier in the case of Islam, and that is why I
say that teaching Islam is trickier. In fact, this specific case is
more obvious than the general one, for while Islam--like any other
living faith--is no petrified monolith, it is at the same time a
bubbling political issue of global proportions. To be sure, no other
religious community in the world receives such extensive, animated,
feverish, and frequent media coverage as do those identified as
Muslims. And more, Islam remains a major concern for world leaders
and policy-makers, generating inter alia an enormous body of
political rhetoric, highly publicized and deeply polarized. Added to
this is the fact that the proportion of American high schools
offering courses on Islam is infinitesimal, something that contrasts
sharply and painfully with the daily journalistic portrayals and
analyses of Islam on the television and in the newspapers. Here we
have an asymmetry leading to a paradox--the paradox that typical high
school graduates, while feeling that they know quite a bit about the
Islamic world, in fact know practically nothing; and what they feel
they know is, at best, a jumble of contextless truncated truths.
What is the result of all this? Evidently, it produces before the
teacher of Islam an intricate jungle of misunderstandings,
stereotyping, polarization, and even fears. But let us pause here to
note that the carriers of this jungle, namely the young students, are
utterly blameless; the responsibility lies rather on the shoulders of
the "grown-ups" of the bigger world existing beyond the boundaries of
school campuses. The students have no choice in the matter: they do
not pack their baggage themselves. They unload before the teacher
what they receive from their environment.
Teaching of Islam to a typical American student body, then,
happens to be a much more serious pedagogical challenge, more
serious, that is, than teaching other world religions. First, there
are problems intrinsic to Islam itself, similar to, though more
intense and complex than, other living faiths. To begin with, the
Western tradition of separation between one's private life and
professional life is still alien to many Muslim students--how can,
they wonder, a non-believer teach, say, the Qur'ân? Or
understand the life of the Prophet? Or speak about the Islamic
obligation of Pilgrimage to Mecca when non-Muslims are not even
allowed to visit it? These questions evaporate only when it is
discovered that the teacher is not only a Muslim, he or she is a
practicing one--a state of affairs which, speaking empirically,
rarely obtains in American universities. This mistrust results in
what I call psychological dislocation, a dislocation that manifests
itself in many ways: some Muslim students become over-aggressive in
the class, heckling throughout the lecture; others turn cynical; some
take a defensive and apologetic posture; some suffer in an intriguing
and glowing silence; and so on.
Then, there is that familiar problem of the believers. Islam, as I
said, is not a monolithic body of doctrine or of people; there exist
deep differences of opinion within the Islamic world, and there exist
different sects. In fact, this very concept of "sects" is a serious
issue in itself. For example, the minority Ahmadiyya group, which
originated in the South Asian subcontinent in the late 19th century,
considers itself to be a Muslim sect; whereas it has been declared a
non-Muslim "heresy" by the bulk of the Islamic world, and this after
a good deal of bloodshed. The problem looms large: an Ahmadî
student who typically insists on considering him- or herself a true
Muslim would feel dislocated if the Ahmadiyya is not included by the
teacher among Muslim sects. But if it is so included, the majority of
Muslim students would condemn the teacher for what they see as a
gross misrepresentation of Islam. Here we have a formidable challenge
for the teacher: how to construct a critical framework of pedagogical
methodology that, on the one hand, ensures fairness, accuracy, and
balance; and, on the other, promises a high degree of sensitivity to
the full range of differing opinions, perspectives, and affiliations
represented among the believers in the class audience.
But this does not exhaust the baggage students bring with them.
There remains what is by far the most daunting challenge--the
challenge of cracking through the hardened crust of popular
perceptions of Islam. Here the teacher faces double jeopardy: to
begin with, there exists typically a profound psychological
polarization between believers and non-believers among the audience
in an introductory Islam course. We know all too well that the
mention of Islam evokes terrifying images in the minds of most
non-Muslim students who frequently expect to hear from the teacher
not so much about the religious, doctrinal, theological, and cultural
features of Islam, but rather specifically about hijackings,
terrorism, violence, fundamentalism, polygamy, and veiling. To be
sure, I have noticed the impatience of some students when I talk
somewhat at length about the diction and stylistics of the
Qur'ân and its legislative and ethical contents; or about the
normative status of Prophetic Traditions; or about the structure,
function, and principles of Islamic jurisprudence; or about the
sources of Islamic ethics. These blameless students feel that all
this is too long a prologue to the main act: the act in which the
dominating characters are bearded, berobed, and fire-breathing
Ayatollahs of Iran, and state-sponsored terrorists, and shrouded
women of the Middle East, and the rap bands of the Nation of
Islam.
But, then, when the teacher does turn to the contemporary world,
the weight of his or her onus increases further. For here the serious
instructor moves directly against the overwhelming currents of media
sensationalism. The task, after all, is to explain, not to utter
platitudes or invectives. Explanation, let us note, is not apology,
nor is it advocacy, nor, indeed, is it a moral or normative act.
Thus, any respectable scholar teaching the contemporary Islamic world
would construct historical and contextual frameworks, theoretical
perspectives, comprehensive corpora of facts, all this to explain.
For example, the Iranian Revolution of 1979 cannot be explained in
isolation from the turbulent and bloody history of Iran during the
Shah, a messy history with international actors. But if this is done
without due pedagogical reflection and judiciousness, and without
keeping in view the nature of the audience, the teacher's explanation
is likely to be equated with apology for the Ayatollahs, or worse:
with advocacy for "Islamic" violence. This is one horn of the double
jeopardy.
Clearly, when the teacher of Islam attempts to discard the
vilifying trade of stereotyping, presenting Muslims in the historical
context like any other people, the believers in the audience begin to
feel gratified, perhaps exonerated. But if extreme care is not
exercised here, another problem emerges. On the one hand, given the
polarization of opinions typically existing between the Muslim and
non-Muslim students, the teacher in the process of explanation might
set the poles even farther apart. Obviously, a result of this kind
constitutes a very sorry situation. But on the other hand, a
sensitive issue lies in store, begotten by the teacher's elaboration
of what I just said: that Muslims, when represented in the sweep of
history, turn out to be just like any other people. And this brings
us to the other horn of the jeopardy.
The historical observation that Muslims are just like any other
people is grounded in data which have both happy and unhappy
elements. For among other things, it throws into relief the fact that
there indeed are episodes in the fifteen centuries of the history of
Muslims when they have made their own serious lapses; when they have
taken more than a small share in internal intrigues and bloodshed;
when they have not been tolerant of ideological differences; when
they have committed offense to their own doctrinal principles and
axioms. Such critical approach has to be informed by a need to
balance: for otherwise, a psychological crisis is likely to develop
among Muslim students, especially those who are practicing ones.
This jeopardy is similar to the one faced by the teacher of other
living religions, such as, say, Christianity. But it is comparatively
more complex in view precisely of the polarization typically existing
in the audience in an introductory course on Islam. Again, the
insensitive teacher might deepen this polarization, receiving the
flak now from the believers. For now the believers might easily
equate a critical account of the history of Muslims with
apology--apology this time to the non-believer. But it can be worse:
it may even be considered a misrepresentation, based on the reports
of unsympathetic, non-Muslim historians.
Having said all this, let me admit that what I have presented here
is the worst-case scenario. These problems may not emerge all in the
same class, and they may remain feeble enough not to disrupt the
smooth flow of pedagogical discourse. On the other hand, these
problems are not hypothetical; I have myself faced them in the early
phases of my teaching career. And, to be sure, some of my colleagues
who teach Islam do report to me the kinds of crises I have outlined;
and they sometimes approach me for advice. The question arises: What
is to be done to keep introductory Islam courses commotion-free? How
does the teacher win the trust of the undergraduate audience? Over
the years I have reflected hard on these challenges, and I have in
the process developed my own pedagogical system. When my colleagues
ask me to articulate this system by way of advice, I begin by
identifying four mutually supportive pillars on which it rests:
methodology, strategy, sensitivity, and courtesy.
Let me elaborate. As for methodology, every scholar must have one;
but the point is to articulate it and announce it explicitly before
the class audience. Take the question of truth for example. A
historian of religion, insofar as he or she is operating as a
historian, is not concerned with the issue as to whether or not a
given religious belief is true: for instance, a group of people
believe that monkeys are gods, but it is not my concern to judge if
monkeys can be true gods, or if polytheism can be true at all. I am
interested, rather, in the function of these monkey-deities: what
specific role has a faith in these gods played in defining a
religious system; and what are the cultural yields of this faith; and
how do believers make sense of this faith; and what is the nature of
the social and moral ethos it begets; and questions of this kind. But
I am not concerned here with the question of truth. I do not stand
before my audience as a preacher; I stand as a scholar. This
methodological principle--which is a grand principle of my
methodology-- should be made public before the students.
Thus, when comparisons are made, and parallels are drawn, students
ought to be informed that these are not moral or value judgments.
When I compare, for example, the Christian trinity with the radical
monotheism of Islam, my audience is made to understand that here in
the capacity of a university teacher I am not saying that Islamic
monotheism is true monotheism and that the standard Christian idea of
trinity corrupts it. Similarly, when I say that, as contrasted with
Christianity, there exists in Islam no doctrinal clergy and no
official orthodoxy, the students are reminded that my exposition is
not judgmental: that here I do not mean to claim that in some
absolute sense one religious tradition is better than the other. I
find it important to clarify that I am not engaged in a
moral-normative exercise of sifting good from evil and truth from
falsehood, sifting with an implicit appeal to some presupposed
eternal principles. I tell my students that in the classroom my
approach is disciplined--that is, it conforms to the norms of
critical inquiry set by the discipline of Religious Studies as this
field is understood in an institution of higher learning. And in the
same vein I announce that there is no penalty for disagreeing with
me, just as there is no reward for agreeing with me. And more, I
frequently assure my students that they are totally free to express
their own opinions, as free as it gets.
Such methodological declarations prevent many problems, for the
rules of the game are known in advance. Besides, articulation of
methodology is beneficial in its own right both for the teacher and
the students. But there does remain the somewhat informal question of
strategy, my second pillar. Here my concern is an efficient and
credible presentation of my case. Thus, for example, when I move
against the familiar Western misunderstandings of Islam, I buttress
my position, as a matter of strategy, with citations from Western
authorities--highly respected Western authorities whose erudition is
widely recognized and who can in no way be considered apologists for
Muslims. Take the popular view that Islam spread through the sword;
here I quote the dissent of a Bernard Lewis rather than a Fazlur
Rahman, and of a Francis Peters rather than an Ismâ`îl
Farûqî.
But conversely, when I come to the darker side of the history of
Muslims--and here it is clarified that I speak not of moral but
historical darkness--I quote Muslim historians, those Muslims who are
considered to be the unparalleled luminaries of Islamic
historiography: a Tabarî or an Ibn Khaldûn, rather than a
Philip Hittie or a William Muir. This conveys a sense of credible
balance to my scholarly position. To be sure, this strategy is not a
ploy of clever salesmanship; on the contrary, it adds to the rigor of
the discourse by providing a principle of source selection, a
principle which requires the use of academically respectable and
recognized primary and secondary sources.
The need for a wise and well-meaning strategy becomes particularly
urgent when one deals with intensely sensitive and controversial
issues. I spoke above of the Ahmadiyya's Muslim self-identity in the
face of its fierce exclusion from the pale of Islam by a vast
majority of Muslims--this is a case in point. Does the teacher
include this group among Muslims? My strategy here is to declare at
the very outset another methodological principle: Islam is what
Muslims say it is, and Islam ought to be what Muslims say it ought
be; just as the American constitution is what Americans say it is,
and the American constitution ought to be what Americans say it ought
to be. To examine a body of doctrines and principles in isolation
from the way it is received and understood by its primary followers
is, in my view, a mere pedantic exercise empty of historical
content.
Thus, after tracing the history of the emergence of the Ahmadiyya,
and after presenting it on its own terms, I tell my students of the
grounds on which the overwhelming majority of Muslims condemned it as
what they considered a mischievous intrigue against Islam; and I end
by pointing out that following several bloody incidents, most Islamic
governments have officially excommunicated this group: that, in other
words, the bulk of Muslims do not recognize the Ahmadiyya as a Muslim
sect. And here I leave the matter. Similarly, when I deal with
controversial issues which are historically distant, I likewise let
Muslim authorities have the final say: a typical example is the vexed
question of the Muslim treatment of the Jewish clans of Medina during
the time of the Prophet of Islam. I handle this question in two
steps: first, I place the matter in its fuller historical context
invoking several non-Muslim scholarly sources; then, I present the
Muslim explanation of the events, using a range of standard Muslim
sources. Thus, again, I end by expounding what Muslim themselves have
to say about the matter; and again, at this juncture I lay the matter
to rest.
Strategic considerations are equally important when we deal with
today's Islamic world. To be sure, every serious teacher of Islam has
been mercilessly exercised by this whole contemporary question of
jihâd, militancy, terrorism, violence, and fundamentalism,
given the preconceived pictures typically existing in the minds of
the young audience. Here I find it most useful to issue several
disclaimers, announced expressly and in advance: That in dealing with
these issues my primary preoccupation is not moral, rather it is
historical. That my chief aim is to provide contextual explanations;
and explanation in this critical sense is not meant to be advocacy or
apology. That here in the academy we do not support violence,
bigotry, discrimination, or hatred. That we do not promote violations
of fundamental principles of human liberty and freedom. That we have
no tactical political axe to grind. And that, above all, our
conclusions, generalizations, and views are not presented as
incontrovertible truths to be accepted uncritically. These advance
disclaimers prevent a great deal of potential misunderstandings, and
more: they help develop a sense of trust on the part of students.
Let me now turn to my third pillar, sensitivity. It goes without
saying that every teacher is virtually duty-bound to operate with
heightened sensitivity to the range of differing opinions, outlooks,
and sensibilities of his or her student audience. In fact, what I
have already said effectively takes care of much of this. But here I
wish to address a specific issue concerning the believers, an issue I
referred to in the very beginning: that among other things, it is
some private concern which generally motivates believers to explore
their own faith in a college course. This concern often manifests
itself in what may be called the "believer's agenda"; but let me
illustrate this. Some of my Muslim students, I have noticed, are from
the beginning interested in certain specific questions, practically
to the exclusion of all else: the question of women's rights in Islam
typically looms large. Some other believers focus throughout on
certain tenaciously-espoused sectarian positions and vantage points
which they are wont to defend. Yet others simply wish to corroborate
what they hear in a mosque. A teacher ought to remain sensitive to
these concerns, for they merit recognition and support rather than
dread and suppression. To be sure, I do encourage the believers to
pursue their agenda--but, then, along with my blessings I also
provide professional guidance, and it is this guidance which is the
crucial thing here. The agenda should receive a careful intellectual
nourishment from the teacher so that it is articulated, developed and
defined--and carried out with critical control. Such sensitive
nourishment generally produces very happy results, happy not only in
terms of pedagogical rigor, but also in existential and scholarly
terms.
Finally, a word about courtesy, the last of the four mutually
supportive pillars of my pedagogical system. Again, all teachers are
duty-bound to be courteous anyway. But in dealing with a living
religion, and particularly if it happens to be Islam, certain
peculiar issues emerge on the horizon which require a careful
identification. Muslims, until this day, use standard honorific forms
of address and utter deferential salutations whenever they name
sacred figures and personages in their tradition. For example, the
Qur'ân is generally, "The Noble Qur'ân"; God is referred
to as, "Allâh, May He be Praised and Exalted!"; the names of
the Companions of the Prophet of Islam are always followed by the
invocation, "May God be Pleased with Him/Her!"; and so on. But by far
the most important one, and here we are dealing with a highly
sensitive issue, is the case of the Prophet himself: in the universe
of Islam, his name is always--uncompromisingly-- followed by a
deferential formula, "Upon Whom be Peace!"
It is understandable that a teacher of Islam may not be able to
stretch his or her courtesy to the degree so as to utter these
invocations each time a revered name is spoken. But I think it is
important to point them out to the class, and thereby recognize them;
and by the same token it would be a profoundly touching gesture of
courtesy to the Muslim students if indeed these formulas are
declaimed here and there, especially upon a first naming. To be sure,
the case of uttering the name of the Prophet deserves the fullness of
the teacher's courtesy. On the other hand, this needs a balancing
gesture: the same sense of courtesy ought to be extended to the
sacred and respected entities of all religious traditions: be they
clerics, rabbis, heroes, objects, or gods.
I must now acknowledge at once that this largely informal account
in no way constitutes a manual for the teachers of introductory
courses on Islam. It is intended neither to be comprehensive nor
authoritative; nor indeed does my system come with any warranties.
All I can claim is that this system has worked for me.
Textual
Representation and Representation of Text
Reflection
on/through Comparison
Mark A. Berkson
It has already happened a number of times. There is a bright,
motivated senior in one of my sections. Towards the end of the class,
I ask him or her what next year's plans are. The answer will often be
"I'm going to law school" (although one could substitute investment
banking, management consulting, etc.). I then ask, "What aspect of
the law are you interested in? Why have you chosen that career path?"
The response will be something like, "I'm not really interested in
the law. It's just that I don't know what else to do. A lot of my
friends are going to law school, and my parents think it's a good
idea. At least the money's good for lawyers."
In contrast to the students' utter lack of thought about one of
the most important decisions they have made in life thus far, they
have put a great deal of thought into how best to accomplish the
goal. Most have known exactly what to do to position themselves well
for a career they're not even sure they want. They have received
excellent grades, have done well on the standardized exams, have good
recommendations and are skilled at the interview process. They have
all the right answers even if they don't believe in them.
Each time such a situation occurs -- and it occurs far too often
-- I reach the same conclusion: these students have missed out on a
crucial aspect of their university education. What does this have to
do with the teaching of religion? Everything -- or so I will
argue.[15]
The American university system is training a nation of means-ends
thinkers. The worlds of business, law, management, politics and
science are filled with highly skilled problem-solvers. Whenever the
government sounds the alarm about a crisis in education in this
country, they point to how far behind the Japanese or Europeans our
students are in math or science. While our emphasis on
problem-solving has created one of the most technologically advanced
societies on earth, the advancement has not seemed to carry over into
the realm of our humanity.
While many can find the means to almost any end, few direct their
attention to the ends themselves, which include the ends of their
particular company or profession, and more importantly of their own
lives. The problem seems to be captured in the distinction between
intelligence and wisdom. In almost every sector of the American
landscape -- Wall Street, the Beltway, the academy, Silicon Valley --
there are numerous people of exceptional intelligence. They are
quick, creative and driven. But, I would contend, there is a
dangerous lack of people who truly possess wisdom. While an in-depth
discussion of the distinction between intelligence and wisdom is far
beyond the scope of this essay, it seems to me that a central element
of the latter that is often missing in the former is reflection. Not
calculation, computation, or instrumental reason, but reflection.
Although means-ends thinking may be a part of it, the type of
reflection I am referring to -- the type that distinguishes people of
true depth as opposed to those that, for example, merely get good
grades -- is reflection on ends, on the most important things in
life.
Perhaps the most important element in such reflection is
self-reflection, which centers around (ultimately, though not always
explicitly) the question, What is the best way to live? or How should
one live? This requires that we look closely and seriously at
questions such as, What is a human being? or What is the nature of
the self?
The Importance of Comparative Religion
Exploring such questions is one of the most important reasons to
study religion. And this is one of the reasons I disagree with
Jonathan Z. Smith, who argues that the subject matter of the
introductory course "is of secondary interest (indeed, I suspect it
is irrelevant)."[16] I take
him to mean that the fact that we are teaching religion is not
important, as long as we give the students certain skills, in
particular reading, writing and speaking. In fact, Smith writes that
"there is nothing distinctive to the issue of introducing
religion."[17] I would argue
that since an introductory course is the only place that many
students will ever be exposed to other religious traditions, and
because the study of the "content" of a religion, in particular its
world-view and normative thought, is critically important for
stimulating reflection, the "religious content" should be central to
the course. For it is within religious texts, articulated by the
great religious thinkers, that the ultimate questions are posed and
grappled with, and that answers are offered. By standing on the
shoulders of religious giants, we gain a vastly expanded, and often
breathtaking, perspective on the world. When we encounter these
texts, we are given compelling visions of what the best human life
is, what the human self is (if there is one), and how the self
relates to itself, to others, to nature and to the cosmos.[18]
Students in a religious studies course have a unique opportunity
to reflect on these fundamental issues; and they will be doing so not
only in the company of a professor and fellow students, but with the
guidance of the greatest minds working through these most important
issues. While many students might sign up for a religious studies
course because it fulfills a distribution requirement, or out of mere
curiosity, it can also be the opportunity for an existential
encounter with powerful alternative visions of the world and our
place in it. As much as possible, we as teachers should try to bring
about such an encounter. While we are certainly not trying to convert
anyone to any particular way of looking at the world, we are trying
to facilitate the kind of encounter that can act as a catalyst to a
deepening self-understanding -- one that stimulates sustained
reflection and develops imagination, empathy and a greater awareness
of human possibility.
I believe that the comparative study of religions can accomplish
this task in a uniquely powerful way. A deep, honest encounter with
an "other" can expose the "false fixities" of one's own way of living
and thinking. It can call into question one's most deeply held
assumptions and engender a type of intellectual and spiritual
exploration that is the fount of true reflection.
The student may come to see that there exists a genuine plurality
of human goods, a multiplicity of forms of human excellence (this is
brought to light by studying the exemplars held up by the world's
religious traditions, figures as varied as Sakyamuni, Confucius,
Augustine and Maimonides).[19]
Hopefully, we will also show that this is a bounded plurality; that
not "anything goes," and that there are ways of thinking about better
and worse-and truly unacceptable-lives. (In fact, it is hard to find
a religious tradition that is truly relativistic in the crude sense.)
This means that in addition to showing students different religious
visions, we must also help them develop the necessary skills not only
to appreciate them, but also to critique them. What we must aim for
is not to have the students suspend judgments in the light of
plurality, but rather to hone their ability to make better
judgments.[20] But here, too,
content matters, for studying the methods (in addition to the
visions) of religious thinkers can make us better at ways of thinking
most of us already, implicitly, employ (e.g. reading Aquinas) or can
radically undermine certain forms of thinking and present powerful
alternatives (e.g. reading Zhuangzi).
It is not necessarily the case that the student's view will be
challenged by the religious view being studied, for many students
have not yet developed any well thought-out picture of the self and
the world. Many people's views on the most important issues are
inchoate or unarticulated. One of the most important things the study
of a religious tradition can do for students is simply to get them to
articulate their beliefs about these issues. Just getting clear about
what we think is a critical first step in the process of
self-reflection. Confronting a challenging religious vision will
force the student to ask him or herself, "What do I think about
that?" Such an encounter makes students become articulate about what
they believe, which often means discovering or developing a view on
an important issue. For a student who has never thought through these
issues, the encounter with a religious vision can show how thinkers
organize their lives around certain ideals and principles which have
a profound consequence for their lives. The study of religion will
not only challenge those students that have a different worldview,
but will make those that have no articulate, well thought-out
position wonder what they might be missing without it.[21]
Confronting the "Other"
What attitude or disposition toward the ends that other religious
traditions pursue should we aim to cultivate in our students? In
order to truly see these ends as goods, the student must learn to see
them as perfective of the human being, as capable of providing
fulfillment and humanity to the individual and society. Given that
different religious traditions often pursue radically different ends,
the student will ultimately recognize that there is a plurality of
human goods. How, though, can a reflective individual see an end
under such a description (i.e. "perfective of the human being") --in
other words gain a deep appreciation for the goods represented by a
certain type of spiritual life -- and still decide not to pursue it?
Lee Yearley offers an answer to this in the form of a uniquely modern
religious virtue, that of spiritual regret.[22]
One who cultivates this virtue recognizes a religious good, and to
some extent feels the power of its pull, yet chooses not to move
toward it or actualize it in his or her own life.
The modern sensibility that makes spiritual regret possible is the
recognition that true human goods exist which may not be available to
oneself, but which are still perfective of others qua human beings.
It recognizes that we all unavoidably live partial lives, where the
element of necessity, our facticity, moves us irrevocably in certain
directions. Historical, cultural, ethnic, and other factors make some
goods simply unreachable for us; they are not real options if we are
to remain ourselves. At the same time, we recognize that our own
culture and tradition makes certain goods available to us, and these
are the ones we must pursue. At a certain point, we must commit to
our own real possibilities and follow a path toward a good that is
fulfilling of us as we are. We recognize that we have an identity,
and that to move toward a good that is too "other" would
fundamentally change who we are.
The attitude we take toward the goods we recognize but cannot
possess, and thus will not move toward, is a complex one. On the one
hand, there is a type of joy that lies behind spiritual regret, a
celebration of the diversity of human possibilities that manifests
itself in the plurality of human goods. This is accompanied by a
feeling of sadness, for those who truly feel the existential pull of
a profound human good must also feel the sense of loss when they
recognize that it can never be theirs. The best that we can do is
cultivate a deep appreciation for that good -- in effect to share in
it by appreciation -- which is why imagination is such an important
part of the process. The regret also comes from the realization that
being human involves recognizing a finitude that ensures no
individual can ever possess "the good" in its entirety; the most any
of us can hope for is a movement toward our own good supplemented by
a deep appreciation of the goods of others.
One will not remain unchanged by the encounter with the goods of
others. When the range of human possibilities opens up for one, and
when another good is recognized as possible for human fulfillment,
one's own notion of what it is to be human is inevitably transformed.
While one might continue to pursue one's own good, it will be done
with a renewed sense of the partial nature of that good from the view
of humanity; in fact, the nature of the good itself might change in
the course of the encounter. The space opened up by spiritual regret
is the locus for some of the most important forms of
self-reflection.
Spiritual regret changes who one is because it involves a new
choice, a choosing of oneself anew in light of options of which one
was previously unaware of. Even if one chooses to reject it, or
modify and incorporate some of it, one is still transformed. Living
without spiritual regret is like walking down a trail never realizing
there were crossroads. One who follows the same path but is aware of
alternatives chooses her path and because of this leads a different
kind of life, for she has a different self-understanding.
The Comparative Imperative
How do we help students cultivate this virtue? In teaching
comparative religion, our imperative is to walk the fine line between
the Scylla and Charybdis of domestication and exoticization. Each one
provides an easy escape from the task of a true encounter. In the
former, one concludes that the other good is, in reality, the same
good as (or at least not in tension with) one's own. It is a denial
of radical difference and incommensurable plurality, and in the end
fails to see the richness and power of the other good. One tames a
potential challenge to one's way of life by smoothing it out until it
looks enough like one's own to avoid confrontation. In the latter,
one keeps the good at a safe enough distance by carefully packaging
and displaying it as a museum piece or tourist attraction rather than
as a good that might potentially speak to one. It provides fuel for
superficial cocktail party conversation which, in effect, sanitizes
it for one's own spiritual protection. At best, one might see it as a
good for humans qua Chinese, or qua Ancient Greeks, but certainly not
qua human being. It is their good, it is fascinating and different,
but it is not compelling to me.
Spiritual regret rejects both of these escapes by seeing the other
as both radically different and a compelling human good. The
domesticator convinces himself that he is not, in fact, failing to
move toward that good. The exoticizer never considers the good as a
possibility for himself, so he does not even get to the point of
having to reject movement toward it. Those who take the radical other
seriously fail to move toward that good only with the deepest sense
of regret that choices must be made, and with the awareness that we
all must live partial lives.
Teaching Methods
What I am advocating, then, is an approach which emphasizes the
comparative study of religion as an existential encounter, in
particular one that fosters reflection on life's most important
questions, provides competing visions as candidate answers to those
questions, and develops the intellectual capacities to critique them,
adjudicate among them (or to know when disputes cannot be
adjudicated) and make meaningful choices. I am also arguing that the
study of religion is uniquely important because it alone poses these
questions and offers these answers in such powerful, beautiful and
compelling ways.[23]
This picture generates a number of specific approaches and
positions in teaching, three of which I will briefly mention here.
First, this suggests an approach that could be described as an
"imaginative insider's vision". More and more, religious studies
departments are being asked to justify their continued existence. The
question is often, "Why should there be a separate religion
department if religion is studied in numerous other departments, e.g.
history, anthropology, psychology, literature, etc.?" While I believe
there are a number of answers to this question (including the
importance of the multi-disciplinary approach that religious studies
scholars bring to their topic), one is the need to enter into a
conversation with particular traditions from, as far as possible, the
inside. We are not just studying, for example, what Buddhists did in
Tang China, or what happened to Buddhism in Kamakura Japan, although
these things are truly important. We should try to show our students
why this vision has been so deeply compelling and profoundly moving
for so many human beings in so many different cultures for over two
millennia. A student should see how Nagarjuna, Wonhyo, or Shunryu
Suzuki views the human condition, what type of life they feel is the
highest form of human flourishing, what spiritual practices they
recommend for transforming ourselves or realizing our true nature.
Certainly, as noted above, we should provide the students skills with
which to critique the visions they study (this seems to be what Smith
is emphasizing)-- skills which are often provided by the traditions
themselves (which is why it is important to show that the ongoing
conversations that define traditions often involve passionate
conflict) -- but first they must learn to appreciate the vision of
life these thinkers represent.
This requires the development of a key capacity for any human
being, imagination, which is developed in the making of analogical
connections between religious pictures and entering into another way
of looking at the world and the self. We learn to see our face in the
face of an "other" while still preserving and appreciating the
radical difference. The development of the imagination (as opposed to
instrumental reason, analytical skills, etc.) is a critical part of
cultivating empathy, which is a precious and rare capacity. Learning
to truly appreciate (not merely tolerate) that which is radically
"other" will allow one to experience the truth of the statement "I am
a human being. No other human being do I deem a stranger." Hopefully,
not only will the student learn to appreciate the vision of a great
religious text, but also that of the person across the seminar table.
Where a student differs with each, hopefully he will learn to work
through these differences in a productive and deep way, not afraid to
challenge, but always maintaining an attitude of respect that arises
from seeing the possible goods in a picture that one does not
possess. What better place than religious studies to learn to do what
America must learn to do to survive: work through passionately held
differences with civility and sophistication?
Second, it is an argument for depth over coverage. Deeply
confronting one powerful vision, such as that of Dogen, is a more
effective, potentially transformative experience than being able to
name all of the patriarchs or schools of Buddhism. While basic
coverage is important to give a student a sense of the overall
tradition and to locate the specific thinkers and texts culturally
and historically, the aim should be to bring the student into a deep
conversation with a thinker or tradition.
Third, this is an argument (contra Smith, again) that specific
content matters. Smith claims that in an introductory course "there
is nothing that must be taught, there is nothing that cannot be left
out."[24] While I agree with
much of his article (particularly, that "less is better"), I would
contend that certain texts are required, and for two reasons. First,
since we want students to encounter the depth of a tradition or
vision, we must give them the texts that most powerfully and
beautifully convey that vision -- which is an important reason that
such texts have survived and become classics. Second, to truly
encounter another culture, to take its visions seriously, a student
must work with the texts that matter the most to that culture. I
would argue that any course on classical Chinese thought must
include, for example, the Analects, the Mencius, and the Zhuangzi.
Students who take a course on classical Chinese thought that leaves
out these texts have not seen what mattered to the ancient Chinese,
have not entered into their conversation and understood what was at
stake in it. Even if, as Smith wants, the students have improved
their reading and writing skills, they have missed perhaps their only
opportunity to truly encounter the visions that have shaped a rich,
enduring culture, visions which speak to all of humanity.
Encountering Resistance
We are trying to show students that a plurality of possible human
goods exists. The students may resist this notion for two reasons,
based on two alternative ways of viewing the world in regard to the
presence of human goods. The first is the belief that only one good
exists, and is the good for all human beings, the sole way to
fulfillment and completion. This was the dominant view in many
pre-modern cultures, and many hold to it passionately today. The
students who hold to this will reject other visions as, at best
lesser or distorted versions of their own good, and at worst examples
of human error or deformation.
But this is unlikely to be the prevailing attitude among modern
students, for the primary modern problem is a sense that there are no
goods at all. Rather than think in terms of goods that are to be
moved toward -- a conception that requires a sense of looking outside
ourselves for the promise of fulfillment that moves us (which
involves the notion of passivity; we are drawn toward that which
perfects us) -- our society is dominated by those who think in terms
of desires that we follow and fulfill. In the absence of any end that
we should pursue, we have merely desires to be satisfied; one's only
guide is what one wants at any given time. It is this model that
underlies much of decision theory and procedural notions of
rationality: we calculate means to satisfy preferences. Rationality
is bound up with thinking about means. As desires can change over
time, and often conflict even at a given time, one will have no sense
of a continuous narrative that would constitute the self.
What is puzzling is that most moderns conceive of the fulfillment
of desires as a more "active" way of thinking about movement than
being drawn toward a good (which is "passive"); yet Thomas Aquinas
points out that being a simple follower of desires is another kind of
passivity, a more slavish kind where one is led by impulses as if
they were vectors that simply propelled one in any direction
whatsoever. Without a meaningful end, there are no criteria with
which to judge some desires as preferable to others; thus, the
intensity or quantity of desires is all that is left. With such a
model, individuals are left running faster and faster on a treadmill
to keep themselves from noticing that they are not getting anywhere.
When there is no destination, all one can do is run in place.
Encountering religious models shows that there are fundamentally
different ways to conceive of the self and its dispositions.
Dealing with these two forms of resistance will require different
approaches, which is a topic for another essay. In both cases,
though, we must strive to present a sympathetic, compelling account
of spiritual visions that will lead the student to see these visions
as containing true human goods and examples of human flourishing.
This will require a shift in ways of conceiving the world. For the
first kind of resistant student, this means entertaining the
possibility that there are other forms of life that are fulfilling of
human beings. While the student who embraces a narrowly uniform
conception of the good (e.g. some who identify strongly with an
exclusivist religious vision) can never accept this premise
completely-and we should not push anyone to do so-it is important to
move someone closer to being able to accept other ways of life as
representing human excellence, as truly human alternatives; perhaps
this means showing that there is at least enough shared by the
religious visions so as to allow them to mutually recognize forms of
excellence in each other. For the second kind of resistant student,
it means just learning to think in terms of goods at all. While many
students will still hold tightly to the desire-based model, at least
they will see that it is merely one model among many, and one with
potentially serious flaws.
There is a kind of resistance (which is actually a
"non-resistance") which is quite difficult to combat because it hides
behind a seemingly benign tolerance, one that is based on what Lee
Yearley has called "bourgeois relativism", a form of tolerance that
avoids any kind of true encounter at all.[25]
Very well-intentioned students who hold tightly to a crude relativism
could face a radically "other" religious vision and, rather than
resist or reject it, merely respond (as some literally have), "That's
cool. But that's their thing. I have mine." This is a failure to see
what is truly at stake in such confrontations. For these students, we
hope to engender some form of resistance, to show them the challenge
that is posed to their way of thinking and living, even if they do
not recognize or acknowledge it at first. Lionel Trilling writes
about this beautifully:
(T)o some of us who teach and who think of our students as the
creators of the intellectual life of the future, there comes a kind
of despair. It does not come because our students fail to respond to
ideas, rather because they respond to ideas with a happy vagueness, a
delighted glibness....When that despair strikes us, we are tempted to
give up the usual and accredited ways of evaluating education, and
instead of prizing responsiveness and aptitude, to set store by some
sign of personal character in our students, some token of individual
will. We think of this as taking the form of resistance and
imperviousness, of personal density or gravity, of some power of
supposing that ideas are real, a power which will lead a young man to
say what Goethe thought was the modern thing to say, "But is this
really true -- is it true for me?"[26]
The Possibility of Crisis
If the students are exposed to other powerful religious visions,
they should see that our cultural nomos, the order which we take for
granted, is merely one possible grid thrown over the infinite
possibilities of existence. Such an experience can be deeply
unsettling, for it exposes the constant but hidden presence of anomie
and forces us to confront human possibility and freedom. For some
students, this can cause a great disturbance and even precipitate a
true crisis. Thus, if we are going to teach religion with this
existential aim, we must ask the question, Are undergraduate students
prepared for this kind of crisis? Are we, as teachers, prepared to
help them? Is this entire approach crossing the boundary of
responsible pedagogy?
I would argue that, at its heart, the university experience must
involve some form of this unsettling experience if it is to be at all
meaningful. When one chooses to enter a university, part of the
bargain is that one is going to open oneself up to serious
challenges. For many students, this may have never occurred up to
this point. And for many others, if they do not have the experience
in college, they may have it at a far more difficult time, when too
many irrevocable choices have been made.[27]
We are not here to reassure students that their choices are good
ones, but to show them the possibilities and give them the tools to
make truly reflective choices rather than live an unconscious and
inauthentic life.
At the same time, however, we must be very sensitive and attuned
to a student's particular situation. For many students, the
transition to college can already be a time of crisis, and often
students must deal with a number of personal traumas while they are
there that might make them particularly fragile at certain
times.[28] With certain
classes, it might even be a good idea to give a short caveat at the
beginning stating that certain issues in the course might strike deep
chords with some students, and that they will have to deal with some
important existential questions. If they are not prepared for this,
or are unwilling to go through this process, they might not want to
take the course. And if particular students approach you individually
and say, for example, that they take the Bible to be a sacred text
and that probing its contradictions and various theories of
authorship is a problem for them (as has happened to teachers I
know), then you must decide when (and how hard) to push a student to
challenge himself, and when to simply suggest that he might be better
off dropping the course. This should also remind us that we should
always be available for our students and approachable; bringing about
existential reflection can lead to some important conversations
during office hours-e.g. how a student who has lived with naive
assumptions about religious texts all of his life can come to terms
with certain methods of interpretation. Professors might want to
bring these issues to the attention of teaching assistants, and
prepare them for the possibility that they may have to face these
issues (probably not often, but even if it is once, thinking about
the issue is worthwhile).[29]
Let me conclude this section with a thought experiment. Let us
assume that, during a course on Buddhism, a student comes into your
office and tells you that she has found herself powerfully drawn to
the Buddhist monastic vision. Not only has she withdrawn her law
school applications, but she has decided to drop out of college and
move to Tibet indefinitely (imagine, also, the phone call that you
might receive from her parents upon learning that you are the teacher
that opened her up to the beauty of the Buddhist vision). How should
you respond?
While such situations might be rare, they are possibilities given
what we are teaching and how I am advocating we teach it. My feelings
on this are ambivalent, and at this point I can say with certainty
only that we should think about and discuss situations like this. For
now, I will only mention some preliminary thoughts. First, situations
like this should make us reflect on our own career choice, for we
should be able to give a convincing account of why the academic
enterprise is part of the good human life. We should be able to
present a case to our students that despite the appeal of other
visions, there are goods that can only be realized in higher
education, and that these goods should be a part of most kinds of
flourishing lives.
Ultimately, however, the student may still decide to leave. And
this is not necessarily a cause for alarm or regret. If we believe in
the profundity of what we teach (not in the sense that a particular
religion is the "right" or "true" one, but that these religious
visions represent forms of human excellence), then we must be willing
to accept this result and entertain the possibility that this will be
deeply fulfilling for the student. Maybe she sees the significance of
what we are teaching in an even deeper sense than we do. And who
among us has not felt the pull of a religious vision or in fact acted
on it? Perhaps the student is not being rash but is simply being
honest or courageous.
This brings us to an important point that I hope will temper much
of what I have said: As teachers, our influence over students is
significant but extremely limited. I am not so deluded as to think
that the kind of existential encounter I hope to bring about, (or the
kind of situation represented in the thought experiment above, which
I do not aim for, but must accept the possibility of) will occur with
any kind of frequency. More likely, the type of students who will
respond to this approach in any immediate way are quite rare. A
student must be prepared for such an encounter to occur; at most, we
are simply catalysts for the event. If the student decides to leave,
there are most likely many other factors at work and the timing is
right for such an encounter. There are probably reasons beyond what
we could fathom.
If the type of existential encounter I aim at is likely to be so
rare, why do I emphasize this approach to teaching? First, I believe
that we should aim as high as possible when teaching at a university;
we should hope to connect with those students who are open to the
possibility of a true encounter with another religious tradition, not
those who are merely there for the credits. At the same time, I
believe that those students who do fall in the latter category will
still benefit most from this approach. While the response may not be
immediate, I believe that we are planting seeds that may come to
fruition later, often at unexpected times or in subtle, mysterious
ways. (This has happened to me a number of times, where the full
impact of a text or thinker I encountered as an undergraduate only
struck me years later, with surprising results). I think that all
students in the class will have a better learning experience if they
see how engaged we are with the tradition; we must communicate not
only the "facts" about the tradition, but why we have found it so
powerful so as to devote a substantial portion of our life to
thinking about it. We must show how we are moved by it, and also show
that our enthusiasm is not tempered (but is rather expressed) by how
vigorously we critique aspects of that tradition.
In a sense, I see this type of religious studies as walking
carefully between the type of advocacy or apologetic often found in
seminaries (what might be associated with "first naivete"), and the
attitude of many who view religion with suspicion, irony or outright
hostility (this might be a form of "anti-naivete", which could argue
for a pure social-sciences/reductionistic approach to religion). We
must aim to cultivate what Ricoeur calls the "second naivete", which
(re)discovers meaning in religious visions without abandoning
critical method (I believe both devout members of religious
traditions as well as those who belong to no tradition -- including
atheists -- can cultivate second naivete).[30]
Second naivete incorporates elements from both sides: a true
appreciation of the position of those who hold to the first naivete,
what we called the "insider's perspective"; and critiques from
numerous perspectives (historical, literary, political,
psychological, sociological, philosophical, etc. -- perspectives
which, I should add, can be of just as much value in the other aspect
of this approach, the "appreciative" side, as in the "critical side".
In reality, no clean separation can be made. Each involves the
other). All of this is a way of saying that religious studies
operates in a realm of powerful tensions: the familiar and the
strange, the appreciative and the critical. But these are productive
rather than harmful tensions, and their most valuable product is
reflection. Bringing about such reflection requires teachers to
perform a balancing act.
Concluding Thoughts
Some might see this approach as paternalistic. Rather than merely
presenting material, I am aiming to make my students certain kinds of
people. I suppose I would have to plead guilty to this charge, but I
would argue that education itself is a paternalistic enterprise, and
it is the denial of that fact that has disturbing consequences. I
don't believe aiming to change students is something we should
apologize for. We must face up to the normative aspect of our
project. If we did not believe that we could make ourselves and our
students better people through this kind of inquiry, why, after all,
would we teach?[31]
However, there is the threat of seeing ourselves as "gurus" hoping
to transform or enlighten our students. We should be very aware of
the shadow side of our role as teachers,[32]
and should always try to avoid any kind of crude proselytizing.
Nevertheless, what I aim for is far from this. The kind of people we
should hope to contribute to forming are those who will not
uncritically buy into any view, including the professor's. They will
have a better sense of the variety of possible flourishing spiritual
lives; will see what is at stake in asking and answering certain
questions; will see the variety of methods for examining these
issues. In short, they will have a well-developed critical capacity,
an awareness of issues of interpretation, and a deep appreciation of
and openness to different spiritual visions.
We are not asking our students to adopt any particular religious
view. Rather, we want them to imaginatively see the world from other
points of view and ask each time, What if this thinker is right? What
if this picture of the human condition, the goal of spiritual
cultivation, the vision of the cosmos, is true? This should be a
question that confronts us whenever we pick up a religious text.
While the students might come to reject, for a variety of reasons
(ethical, metaphysical, epistemological) the vision they encounter,
they should see the goods (and the problems) inherent in it. They
should either recognize it as a legitimate model of human excellence,
or be able to give a sophisticated account of why it is not so. In
doing so, they will open up their own beliefs to critical assessment
and theoretical reflection. They will also have better skills and
dispositions to carry this out responsibly, for reading great
religious texts not only shows us the thinker's vision, but also the
way the thinker works through the issues.
Finally, I should note that one of the reasons I am convinced of
the value of this approach is that a class that employed it did, in
fact, change my life. I dropped my plans to go back into the business
world and applied to graduate school in religious studies. It was a
class that made explicit what had been unconscious and implicit in my
thinking. I encountered new visions, and different kinds of questions
and challenges. Some of the traditions I encountered even offered
ways to resolve tensions that had long existed in my own
(unconscious) attempt to combine a variety of Western traditions
(e.g. Aristotelian virtue theory, existentialism, and Enlightenment
liberalism).
In other words, the course not only showed tensions and
contradictions in my thought and exposed all of my dearly held false
fixities, but also forced me, for the first time, to truly reflect on
the most important issues in life. Fortunately, it also gave me the
skills and dispositions to begin doing it fairly well, although I
know that I will spend my life trying to do it better. I had to
unpack my assumptions and work through them in light of a radical
challenge, a task that has become a lifelong project.
The religious studies course is one of the best places in which to
engage in reflection on the most important issues; cultivate the
skills and virtues that allow us to reflect, choose and ultimately
live well; and encounter those traditions and thinkers that provide
us with visions that show us other human goods and forms of
excellence that will always draw us, disturb us, and transform us.
Getting students to undertake this project, what Socrates called "the
reflective life", must be a goal of the university education. As
teachers of religion, we have a special opportunity -- in fact, I
would argue a responsibility -- to make this happen.
Andrew Flescher
A graduate student from Comparative Literature and fellow teaching
assistant told me what he regards as his most important goal in the
classroom: motivating students to think and interpret totally for
themselves. I have heard this aspiration pronounced so often that it
sounds almost like a cliché. The problem with the slogan,
stated in unqualified fashion as above, is that the instructor who
subscribes to it also potentially condones too many cases of
uncritical thinking and uncritical interpretation.
Teachers have the honorable task of enhancing the lives of those
whom they inform combined with the weighty one of helping to shape
their beliefs, and when the latter is done poorly the consequences
are seldom harmless. That Romans, for example, has been traditionally
explained as a treatise on human sin rather than as a letter dealing
with problems of ethnicity, has had real and unfortunate effects on
the history of non-Christian peoples in homogeneous, medieval Europe.
If Romans has been mistranslated, and as a natural consequence
misinterpreted throughout a significant portion of its history, then
as responsible scholars and educators we must see ourselves as
accountable for the tradition of which we are heirs. In this specific
case we would be accountable for the policies and sanctions that were
in part fueled by an incorrect, or at least poorly supported reading
of Romans, policies and sanctions that were especially damaging to
Jews and alienated practitioners of other religions who resisted
assimilation. Through the promulgation of a better supported reading,
the teacher has the ability to contribute to the eradication of
anti-Semitism and other forms of religious discrimination. The
critique of destructive myths, then, becomes a teacher's constructive
tool. It allows her to create new metaphors which appeal to a wider
audience, an audience perhaps alienated by the old reading. In any
case, whichever reading of a text that one prefers becomes very
important. An egalitarian approach, by contrast, sees all
interpretations as one form of a myth or another, in effect giving
equal worth to the arguments for each. The egalitarian justifies her
complacency by engaging in the rhetoric of open-mindedness. I do not
contend that the teacher should be intolerant of the various
recommendations which come her way, nor that she be wary of her
tolerance. Rather, I am advising that when such options come to
light, they should be judged against the standards of good
scholarship by which she learned to abide in her own academic
training.
I hear my Comparative Literature colleague remark that texts have
lives of their own, that the more adaptable they are with respect to
furnishing multiple interpretations, the more deserving they are as
documents due our attention. Interpretations say more about the aims,
biases and insights of interpreters than they do about the texts
interpreted. Consequently, a text is successful simply to the extent
that it serves as a vehicle of expression or as an opening for a
large and diverse audience. Because all interpretations distort the
intended meaning, he argues further, attempts to ascertain the
original author's aims are abrasive and do violence to the text. We
thus best fulfill our roles as educators by receiving graciously each
reading and by resisting conclusions which reduce options. Good
scholarship involves recognizing, even highlighting, competing
alternatives. Progress, for the egalitarian, amounts to giving new
life to old texts rather than entombing them in dominant forms. We
are encouraged to listen to as many voices as possible.
While I appreciate this perspective, there may be some important
weaknesses here. In the setting of our current academic environment,
however, where the many and trendy forms of relativism (good and bad)
are gaining increasing acceptance, these need to be carefully shown.
Such a demonstration is not easy. At least it will entail a
confrontation with some very formidable practical difficulties.
At a modern, liberal university, where participants in any
deliberation can appeal to a number of authorities, arriving at a
"right" answer seems nearly impossible, not just some of the time,
but ever. Yet, history is so often shaped by some interpretation
which emerges as the dominant one. How does a teacher of the
humanities constructively fulfill her role as authority? How does she
privilege this interpretation of a text over that one, while managing
at the same time not to discourage the participation of students
informed by multifarious traditions, each with different commitments
and priorities? How are her students to best benefit from her
experience and insight? Can she ever be justified in directing them
away from the wrong options, the wrong interpretations? If so, can
she still manage to head a discussion in which she comes across
neither as overbearing nor manipulative in a pseudo-Socratic way?
This is all to ask: how can she both gain and deserve the trust of
those whom she hopes to instruct?
Last semester, which was my first semester as a teaching
assistant, I learned how hard these feats are to accomplish. One
mostly laudatory student offered the following critical suggestion on
his section evaluation:
Andrew's enthusiasm was tempered from time to time by silent
stares from his audience. Sections would have been improved had
Andrew not come with an agenda. He directed the flow of conversation
from beginning to end, often in such a way as to arrive precisely
where he had anticipated he would. What we gained by virtue of
competent analysis, we lost due to limited student-student
interaction.
I was initially defensive after reading this comment. Had I let my
students govern themselves more freely, I thought, too much would
have been left up to chance while pertinent issues would have
remained unaddressed. But by refusing to risk this outcome I had
sacrificed something even more important: an environment where the
exchange of ideas was encouraged. What I had intended merely as good
guidance verged on dogmatism. Stylistically, I compromised the appeal
of my delivery, regardless of its clarity and relevance. Many
students, I should say, appreciated that I insisted that we all be
critical of the suggestions we each had to offer. But often it is the
unheard voice, fearing that what it has to say is bound to share a
similar fate as the less-than-persuasive contentions that happen to
have preceded it, which under more welcoming circumstances would
offer the most salient contributions.
As resident expert, or "senior conversation partner"--as I have
heard John P. Reeder, Jr. fondly use the term, the burden of engaging
this particular student falls on my shoulders. The challenge is to
create conditions for inspiring her to want to make herself heard.
Teachers have the complicated chore of adequately fulfilling their
dual roles as authority and mediator. In the former role, the teacher
maintains a certain, even necessary distance; in the latter she must
in some sense be perceived as an equal, eager herself to learn.
Students gain from a teacher's expertise, but perhaps they gain more
by taking advantage of a chance to inform and draw others into a new
understanding, seeing themselves as the authority. Such an
undertaking, of course, presupposes a level of commitment that many
at the undergraduate level would rather not assume. These majority
rest quite comfortably with the traditional lecturer-to-recipient
format of learning. But, to address a central question raised by J.
Giles Milhaven in his contribution to this manual ("Teaching,
Learning and Feeling"), teachers in practice evoke pleasure in
students insofar as they allow them to become involved in the whole
process. The affective and imaginative dimensions of learning, I want
to suggest, are essential to good teaching. It is, for example, when
students see other students respond to their insights and when they
then realize the extent to which those other students would not have
benefited had it not been for their involvement, that they become not
just curious, but passionate. I say this because feedback of this
sort does more to inspire me than anything else.
One can emphasize student involvement in the teaching process and
still believe both 1) that there do exist "better" answers to
questions of interpretation and 2) that their intellectual and
affective acquisition is worthy of any questing scholarly forum. Just
as coming to a seminar with an agenda can jeopardize a student's
trust in a teacher, as I learned first hand, over-tolerance of poorly
supported assertions, which in a seminar setting are too often
permitted to survive unscathed for the sake of provoking the
intellectual and emotional development of the errant participant,
cannot help but annoy and diminish the faith of those others in the
audience who want to see emerge the adjudicator in their teacher.
They, to a certain extent, depend on her to draw upon the resources
of her experience both in her particular academic field and as an
educator in general (e.g. as one capable of directing inquiry). In
this way will their learning be more efficient. Otherwise they would
not feel the need to go beyond the text itself and to the classroom
in the first place (as indeed many do not). Of course, the one
officially in charge will not always be the best judge. This is why
challenges by students are healthy. They clarify persisting
ambiguities and force proponents and defendants to better marshal the
evidence which support what they hold to be true. At the end of the
day, plenty of issues may well remain unresolved, and some of those,
irresolvable.
To be sure, a text protected by double meanings and contextual
considerations to which we as outsiders lack any access may declare
victory over its reader. Yet, this is not a priori true, and so it
does not have to be the case. A significant purpose of scholarship in
the humanities is to provide clues which shed light on context. It
helps, for instance, that we know that a particularly mysterious
phrase from Romans about homosexuality can also be found in the work
of Philo, who wrote during the same period as Paul, and whose
intentions in this case we do have the sufficient contextual evidence
to grasp. It helps to know that according to Kierkegaard, his large
pseudonymous corpus was purportedly conceived all at once, indicating
a grand rhetorical strategy on the part of the author wherein each
work comprises merely one element of the whole. To conceive Fear and
Trembling in isolation, one might not gather from a first reading, is
in part to miss the point of Fear and Trembling. It is precisely
facts like these upon which judgments about the correctness of
interpretations must rely, and it is the teacher's business to make
herself and her students acquainted with as many of those as
possible. As I said before, our history demonstrates that the
privileging of interpretations is bound to occur; it is up to the
teacher to see that it occurs in an informed way.
In the West education tends to be a public affair. When we teach,
Alasdair MacIntyre rightly contends, we teach from an inherited
tradition which, even when we amend it, we are affirming and
endorsing as well. This is important because it acknowledges that
there are norms which govern scholarship, and to administer these
effectively requires practice just as does all good craftsmanship. I
believe good teachers are as the myth says they are: wise people.
They are able to draw upon the resources of their tradition in such a
way as to discern that which might qualify as augmentation, for not
everything will. Rarely if ever is it possible for contributors to
the academy to fail to recognize the debt they owe their
predecessors. The drawback here, some argue, is that by paying
mandatory homage to the pillars in the field, scholars turn education
into an impersonal enterprise. Peter Brown puts the problem nicely
when he observes that under such conditions people learn to "mold
themselves, like clay, carve and polish themselves like a statue (I
use the current images of education) so as to form themselves through
and through according to the very rigid and demanding rules of
exemplary behavior." (Peter Brown, "The Saint as Exemplar in Late
Antiquity," in Saints and Virtues, 1987) One wonders if the bringing
to bear of rigid criteria in evaluating interpretations, criticisms
and so forth stifles the creative aspect to learning.
The significance attached to dialogue in learning helps to assuage
this worry. Feedback from ones peers in a seminar setting--also a
part of the Western legacy--is tantamount to making learning a
dynamic and novel activity. Additionally, the way in which knowledge
learned in the classroom translates into normative forces at work in
society is in a very important sense our concern and not one of our
forerunners. As authority, the teacher situates these concerns; she
links the present to the past. As mediator, in dialogue with her
students, she looks to the future. It is her students who in numbers
take knowledge out into the world and affect personal lives, policy,
public opinion and history. And of course it is the good students who
teach the next generation.
the
Teaching of Religious Ethics[33]
Aaron Stalnaker
Søren Kierkegaard ruminated for years on the most effective
way to communicate ethical and religious knowledge. His solutions
were various, but for much of his authorship he insisted on the
necessity of indirect communication. In this paper I will sketch
Kierkegaard's ideas about indirect communication and subjective and
objective understanding, and then argue that while the dramatic
differences between contemporary America and Golden Age Denmark
require substantial changes in Kierkegaard's prescription for
teaching religious ethics, his central concerns can still provide
helpful guideposts as we reflect on how to teach in the modern
academy.
One of Kierkegaard's pseudonyms, Johannes Climacus, discusses
indirect communication, subjectivity, and objectivity at length in
the Concluding Unscientific Postscript. Climacus draws a stark
distinction between objective and subjective reflection. Objective
reflection abstracts from the individual human being who does the
thinking, moves away from her subjective concerns, thereby making the
person in her distinctness completely unimportant; the degree of this
irrelevance is the measure of the thought's objective truth.[34]
Subjective reflection, on the other hand, "turns inward toward
subjectivity and in this inward deepening will be of the truth, and
in such a way that, just as . . . when objectivity was advanced,
subjectivity vanished, here subjectivity as such becomes the final
factor and objectivity the vanishing."[35]
Here one's particularity as an existing human being is never
forgotten, but instead brought into constant dialectical relation
with whatever ideas one is considering.
Corresponding to the distinction between modes of reflection is a
distinction between essential and accidental knowledge. Climacus
writes, "All essential knowing pertains to existence, or only the
knowing whose relation to existence is essential is essential
knowing."[36] Essential
knowing is the fruit of subjective reflection, and as we will see, is
characterized by an individual's personal appropriation of
ethical-religious communication. Climacus continues, "Therefore, only
ethical and ethical-religious knowing is essential knowing. But all
ethical and all ethical-religious knowing is essentially a relating
to the existing of the knower."[37]
Ethical and religious knowledge concerns how to live; to understand
or to think it is to apply it to one's own life. There is a
distinction lurking here, between what Stephen Evans calls subjective
and existential knowledge, i.e. between the potential and actual
appropriation of subjective reflection, but both are steps on a
single ladder, different stages in one reflective mode.[38]
In contrast to this, when one's particularity is avoided, objective
reflection issues in "accidental" knowledge, such as the truths of
natural science, world history, and veterinary medicine.
Accidental, i.e. objective, knowledge can be communicated directly. A scientist can report the result of his experiment, and does not need to reflect about how to express it. In contrast, conveying subjective understanding is more problematic because the goal of such communication is personal appropriation, or as Climacus says, "reduplication," not rote memorization of formulas.[39] Since a direct form of address assumes that appropriating the information passed along will be easy, so easy that it can be ignored, this will not do for ethical-religious understanding, where a direct mode of presentation tends in general to prevent real appropriation by implying such an incorporation would be effortless.[40] In this case an indirect form is necessary. Direct communication of religious thought is a "fraud."[41] Climacus writes,
Wherever the subjective is of importance in knowledge and appropriation is therefore the main point, communication is a work of art; it is doubly reflected, and its first form is the subtlety that the subjective individuals must be held devoutly apart from one another and must not run coagulatingly together in objectivity.[42]
Indirect communication of ethical-religious knowledge requires
artfulness, subtlety, and self-control. In order to encourage genuine
appropriation on the part of her listeners, a subjective speaker must
avoid a direct presentation; her hearers should think things through
for themselves, rather than parroting her phrases. This is the art of
"setting the other free."[43]
One of Kierkegaard's favorite methods of indirection is
pseudonymous authorship. Kierkegaard aims to distance the reader from
the source of the thought offered for her consideration; she is
forced back onto her own interpretive and evaluative devices, rather
than invited to entrust her faith to someone else, an authority, thus
forfeiting responsibility for her own existence. Climacus's humorous
"revocation" of the Postscript functions similarly. Perhaps the whole
book is a jest; the reader will have to decide for herself. All
devices employed in indirect ethical-religious communication aim at
the individual hearer passionately appropriating the communication in
her inwardness, which is accomplished through her subjective
reflection on the ideas at hand.
Climacus specifies more fully what he has in mind. Ethical
knowledge must be presented as a "live option," a possibility for the
listener.
If actuality is to be understood by a third party, it must be understood as possibility. . . . What is great with regard to the universal must therefore not be presented as an object for admiration, but as a requirement. In the form of possibility, the presentation becomes a requirement. Instead of presenting the good in the form of actuality, as is ordinarily done, that this person and that person have actually lived and have actually done this, and thus transforming the reader into an observer, an admirer, an appraiser, it should be presented in the form of possibility. Then whether or not the reader wants to exist in it is placed as close as possible to him.[44]
When an ethical position is presented as a real existential
possibility, the position is experienced by the listener as a demand
to change her life, which is likely to call forth authentic
subjective reflection. If it is presented as the heroic achievement
of a particular gifted individual, the listener is seduced into
admiration, and after more experience eventually becomes a
connoisseur of "the good," evaluating positions from a safe distance,
i.e. objectively.
What are we to make of these ideas today? First, the temptations
and goals of teaching ethics today are essentially the same as
Kierkegaard's. Directly presenting numerous ethical theories as facts
to be considered trains students to treat ethics as a unique domain
with its own aesthetic standards, and also trains them to avoid
subjective reflection on the existential possibilities such positions
represent, while concentrating on the logical structure and
justification of various positions. Appropriation is forgotten.
"Doing ethics" becomes a special kind of philosophical reflection
with its own exemplars and standards of professionalization. On the
other hand, a contemporary teacher of ethics may seek to engage
students intellectually in what they are reading and hearing, and
this engagement, when the subject is ethics, ideally becomes
existential. Appropriation of ethical ideas in one's life, i.e.
becoming a better person, does not drop out of sight, but instead
becomes the raison d'être of the whole enterprise.
Given that the context for this discussion is the teaching of
religious ethics, a critic might object that I am advocating
proselytizing, however subtle, and that this has no place in a modern
liberal university. Kierkegaard should certainly be understood as a
Christian author whose writings were for Christian purposes. I am
arguing that his ideas have merit outside the context of strictly and
explicitly Christian "upbuilding," and can have a legitimate place in
a genuinely pluralistic community. His ideas about the value of
subjective reflection on ethics and the perils of similar objective
reflection, as well as the necessity of taking these into account
when you try to communicate ethical knowledge, have enduring value,
and can be recast in a contemporary idiom.
In fact, we need to reformulate Kierkegaard's insights because our
current American situation is very different from that of 1840's
Denmark. Kierkegaard perceived his age as one of Christendom
triumphant, where in the eyes of the state and of society everyone
becomes a Christian "as a matter of course," without thinking about
it. Climacus writes,
Because everyone knows the Christian truth, it has gradually become such a triviality that a primitive impression of it is acquired only with difficulty. When this is the case, the art of being able to communicate eventually becomes the art of being able to take away or to trick something away from someone.[45]
This throws new light on the questions at hand. Climacus can
stress that direct communication of ethical truth is a waste of time
because everyone has already heard it. In this special case
communication must be indirect even to the point of destruction of
some received ideas if subjective reflection is to be possible. If
the situation were different, though, different methods might be
necessary. Climacus writes,
As soon as the truth, the essential truth, can be assumed to be known by everyone, appropriation and inwardness must be worked for, and here can be worked for only in an indirect form. The position of the apostle is something else, because he must proclaim an unknown truth, and therefore direct communication can always have its validity temporarily.[46]
When a listener is genuinely ignorant of some ethical truth,
direct communication of that truth can have its place. For Climacus,
and for Kierkegaard, the paradigm case for this is the apostles, but
the gravity of the comparison need not cow us from recognizing the
necessity of tailoring one's teaching to circumstances if it is to be
effective.
Contemporary America, unlike Kierkegaard's Denmark, is an
increasingly diverse society. Different communities and disparate
understandings of humanity exist side by side, and frequently mingle
or collide with one another. In this climate, and especially within
the critical hothouses American colleges have become, students are
often confused and uncommitted, espousing varieties of relativism and
romantic emotivism. Ignorance and incoherence loom, not to mention
nihilism. Furthermore, if one believes that good, even great, human
lives can be intellectually informed by various traditions, then the
task of "setting the other free" demands an especially stern
discipline. The positions and traditions one's students choose to
appropriate may be other than one's own.
Kierkegaardian insights can be put to work in such a situation,
but creativity is required, and certain other tenets of Kierkegaard's
thought will have to be set aside.[47]
I will call my prescription "pseudonymous teaching."
When leading a course covering multiple theoretical standpoints or
traditions, the teacher should dramatically present each position
with maximum force and vividness. This includes two steps: first, an
historically accurate study of the text with a sufficiently complex
description of its context so that the students have some hope of
grasping what the author was attempting to do; second, "translation"
into the most compelling modern version of such a theory one can
imagine, especially if the text makes claims to which contemporary
college students might initially be averse (e.g., the need for
radical self-sacrifice or proper relation to previously unknown
metaphysical systems). This translation is not code for "watering
down" a hard teaching, but rather a metaphor for the passionate
attempt to present the existential possibilities within a text as
real possibilities for the students. In this way one can deliver the
ethical demand of each author in person, as compellingly as possible,
all the while keeping one's own views cloaked in secrecy. This
presentation of existential demands can prompt students to reflect
subjectively on their own lives, to question themselves within a new
framework, and conversely to question the applicability of each new
text to their lives. When this is done well, it can seem as if the
dead have come back to life.
This process should be repeated with each new author or position.
In this way the teacher "retreats" from her students, using her
superior knowledge and philosophical power to present each position
authoritatively, and then backing away, leaving students with the
awareness that a thoughtful person takes this seriously, but without
giving a result to recite unreflectively, or providing a personal
authority to whom one might cede one's soul. In this way the
authority that the teacher displays by means of her erudition and
critical skills is transferred to the texts, and students
intellectually engage the subject matter in a way which might bear
ethical fruit in their own lives. The teacher opens up possibility as
a demand for individual students, which if successful may lead to
soul-searching and partial appropriation, and the desire to learn
more.[48] Equally important
benefits of this method include learning the intellectual virtues of
historical sensitivity, close textual analysis, rational argument,
and continuous work on writing skills through paper assignments.
In this way both direct and indirect communication are utilized in
the service of intellectual development and inward appropriation. The
teacher directly presents unknown authors, texts, or traditions, and
this is as it should be if inquiry into these positions is to get off
the ground. Yet indirection persists in the dramatic presentation of
the demands inherent in possibilities, the concomitant hiding of
one's own assessments,[49] and
the resulting transference of authority from teacher to texts. The
goal of this indirection is the same as Kierkegaard's: to stimulate
subjective reflection.
This assumption of multiple ethical/intellectual identities is
most effective in introductory and intermediate classes. As students
become more knowledgeable, the pseudonymous retreat becomes less
beneficial and can be positively harmful if repeated too long, which
might suggest that a lack of commitment to any position is both
possible and desirable. As the distance between teacher and student
decreases, a more collaborative model of teaching should come to the
fore, and direct expression of one's own views, as one's own, becomes
essential. But when introducing students to powerful thinkers,
especially when they come from cultures either temporally or
spatially distant from our own, this more Kierkegaardian way seems
both appropriate and fruitful.
Mark Unno
"You don't live to get the right theory.
You make use of limited theories to live the right life."
--Unknown
Introduction
In the classroom we as teachers spend much of our time explaining,
analyzing, and debating the factual accuracy, rational coherence, and
overall sense of the texts we present, read, and examine. In a
seminar teacher and students are seated in chairs separated by the
span of the table; in lectures we stand before a seated audience
uniformly facing us. Preparing for class, both teacher and student
have been sitting at desks and bringing our minds to bear on the
readings that will be lectured upon, discussed, and for which papers
will be written. All of this is designed to maximize the sense of
equidistance among the students and the sense of distanced
objectivity; it also subordinates personal contact and engagement to
intellectual demands.
Exams and papers likewise tend to emphasize the importance of
consistency and analytical clarity. Although there is increasing
flexibility in style and genre, assigned paper topics generally place
a premium on theoretical mastery and the careful analysis of textual
evidence.
Thus, within the framework of our institutional practices-in
lectures, discussions, reading texts, and evaluating written work-our
primary mode of engaging undergraduate students is intellectual, and
students naturally strive first and foremost to grasp textual ideas
in terms of their logical relationships and coherence.
The texts that we examine in religious studies, however, often
contain knowledge that was not appropriated in a primarily or
exclusively intellectual mode. Texts conveying knowledge of ritual,
visions, dreams, personal encounters, and the like may appeal to
intuition, emotion, and bodily or somatic awareness as much as to
intellectual understanding. Different genres emphasize different
modes of knowledge. Journals, essays about personal experiences, and
fiction often appeal equally to a differentiated sense of affect as
to intellect. Poetry and works of devotion frequently represent a
blend of intuition and affect. Manuals on ritual and meditation speak
of somatic appropriation. All texts are subject to intellectual
analysis, but the full range of their contents may not be accessible
to the rational intellect alone.
The representation of texts in religious studies occurs at the
historical intersection of complex practices. On the one hand, the
secular, liberal, democratic university based largely on the ideal of
public, equal access to objective bodies of knowledge could not have
been created without the distance and universality thought to be
afforded by the rational intellect. On the other, the content of
texts in religious studies indicate that other modes may be involved.
The intellect has tended to be regarded as objective, while
intuition, affect, and somatic understanding have been relegated to
the problematic sphere of the subjective or even the irrational. Yet
these other modes of knowledge suggest a logic each unto its own,
highly differentiated and consistent within its own sphere.
Of course, it would be an exaggeration to say that these other
modes are completely excluded from undergraduate education. In fact,
it would be impossible to engage students meaningfully in their
subject matter without some appeal to the intuitive sense and
emotional impact of textual ideas. This is especially true in
religious studies. Thus, we intersperse our explanations with
analogies, illustrations, and stories to evoke interest, wonder,
empathetic understanding, appreciation, disgust, and humor in our
students. But there are limits to the extent to which we can ask
students to become engaged. One might explain William James'
conception of prayer in the Varieties of Religious Experience and
convey some intuitive sense of the world of meaning that it
constitutes for him. However, it would be going too far to insist
that students identify with James' sense that prayer is "the very
movement itself of the soul . . . [in] contact with the
mysterious power."[50]
Similarly, one might explain the logic and sense of a Zen Buddhist
meditation manual, but it would be inappropriate to require that
students engage in formal training in meditation techniques.
The religious studies curriculum of the contemporary American
university provides access to a wider range of texts in religious
studies than ever before, but we are far from having worked out the
problem of how and to what extent knowledge of these texts can be
conveyed. This essay represents a preliminary attempt to consider
three questions related to this problem: What is the relationship
between different modes of knowledge in the pedagogy of religious
studies? Whence does the teacher derive her or his knowledge of texts
in religious studies? And how does one bring different texts into
conversation with one another?
The Relationship between Different Modes
Thus far the intellectual, intuitive, affective, and somatic modes
of appropriating knowledge have been mentioned. There may be many
others, but I have found it a useful point of departure to begin with
these four. In terms of working with students towards an
understanding of texts, I have also identified a general sequence of
progression between these modes, although exceptions are frequent
enough. In actual practice there is a shifting back and forth between
modes rather than a smooth linear development, and more than one mode
is usually operating simultaneously. I have nevertheless found the
following schematization helpful.
The first mode of engagement is intellectual, since students
usually seek to work out the conceptual relationships between ideas
before they can fully enter the world of the text.
Once a general framework has been established at this level, the
students can start to explore individual ideas and themes within the
larger context. That is to say, they begin to internalize a map of
meaning by means of which they can intuit the sense and meaning of
individual pieces in light of the whole. A map, however, can be no
more than a crude approximation of the actual landscape.
In order to see what it might be like to actually traverse and
live in the world represented by the text, students need to become
responsive to the shades of emotion found therein; this is probably
the most difficult area to facilitate on the part of the instructor.
In order to engage students and to present a sophisticated rendering
of the text, the teacher must open the possibility to affective
engagement but not coerce students into emotional
identification.[51] It is
difficult, for example, to appreciate the passion with which Simone
Weil pursues her philosophical endeavors without having some inkling
of the suffering undergone by the factory workers with whom she
toiled; at the same time, it would be sermonizing to tell students
that they must confront the class conflicts at work in their own
lives. As mentioned earlier, one means of providing the opportunity
for affective engagement without forcing students is to give
illustrations and analogies as indirect channels of access.
While somatic modes of acquiring knowledge are integral to
athletics, performing arts, and the like, we rarely attempt to engage
students at this level in religious studies. At the same time, many
students become highly intrigued by the possibility of engagement at
the somatic level, such as what it might mean to do meditation. On
the one hand, it is enticing precisely because somatic engagement is
excluded, and students feel that their overburdened minds are cutoff
from their bodies; on the other, somatic knowledge seems to some to
provide a more intimate, deeper knowledge of the ideas represented in
the texts they study.
It should be noted here that somatic engagement does not entail an
exclusively or even predominantly sympathetic attitude towards the
object of study. The practices associated with virtually any idea can
have both positive and negative effects, and one can often gain the
deepest and most critical understanding of these effects at the
somatic level of engagement. The violinist who is competing for a
chair in a major professional orchestra knows intimately both the
beauty of playing Stravinsky's The Firebird and the almost cruel
demands of practice and competition that pervade the professional
world of concert performance. Similarly, some of the harshest and
most incisive critics of religious traditions have come from
adherents and former adherents of these traditions. All of this is
further complicated by the fact that the ideological practices that
have produced texts used in religious studies not infrequently mask
the darker side of the ideas they propound. Peter Berger has
suggested that the true adherent must also be the harshest critic,
one who obeys "the heretical imperative."[52]
This is one reason why the application of external perspectives and
theories to critique ideas represented in a text plays an important
role.[53]
My pedagogical strategy in negotiating the four modes has been to
bring the intellectual and intuitive modes of engagement fully into
the classroom, to open possibilities for affective engagement through
lecture and discussion, and to provide opportunities for deeper
affective and somatic engagement at the individual level when
queried. If a student comes in during office hours expressing
interest in doing Zen meditation, then I will provide information
about nearby meditation centers. If she or he would like to meet a
Buddhist monk, then I can similarly provide information about public
talks and other situations to fulfill their needs. I also offer
advice about things to look out for and further texts they might read
to acquire a broader base of knowledge, but at this point I usually
restrain my avuncular instincts and keep this to a minimum. As
individuals on their own life-journeys, students need to find out
things for themselves.
The Teacher's Appropriation of Knowledge
The issue of how to convey knowledge of texts on various levels
implies a second question, that of whence and how the teacher derives
the knowledge she or he communicates. Graduate training today
involves both research and pedagogy, and while the two are closely
related, they are not always complementary. In graduate research
there is a high degree of specialization, the audience or readership
is usually small and learned, and students learn to qualify their
statements extensively in both papers and at conferences. In
undergraduate pedagogy, especially in lectures, material is presented
at the introductory or intermediate levels, the audience is often
large and highly diverse, and the ability to evoke interest and start
with useful generalizations is important.
In a word, graduate research is significantly devoted to
professional training, while in undergraduate education students are
in a much more exploratory, search mode. For this and other reasons
described by Mark Berkson in his essay, "Reflection on/through
Comparison," effective undergraduate pedagogy depends upon the
teacher's skill in enabling students to enter imaginatively into an
unfamiliar world of textual ideas. In order to do this, we go beyond
the boundaries of our research to draw upon analogies and examples
from daily life with which students can identify. Furthermore, many
of us are required to teach texts outside of our research
specializations.
As we blend the knowledge gained through research with our own
reservoir of experience in order to create an effective pedagogy, we
have to ask ourselves, how accurate is the representation of the text
that we communicate to the students? Unlike some, I do not believe
that there is a single, exclusively correct reading of a text. At the
same time, I think that there are better and worse renderings, as
indicated by Andrew Flescher in his essay, "Teacher as Authority and
Mediator," and just as one can say that there are better and worse
interpretations of a Mozart piano concerto. Like a Mozart concerto,
our knowledge of texts involves the intellectual, intuitive,
affective, and somatic levels, and we can examine our knowledge by
asking ourselves, "On what levels have I appropriated knowledge of
this text, and on what levels can I speak competently?" It is not
that difficult to give a convincing representation of a text to an
audience completely unfamiliar with that text, but it is another
question altogether of whether a particular representation is fair
and faithful.
By continually reexamining our own knowledge at various levels or
modalities, we can gain a greater degree of internal consistency at
the same time that we develop a more effective outward presentation.
In talking about Alice Walker's In Search of Our Mother's Gardens, I
might draw on my own experiences of encountering prejudice; I can set
the appropriate sense of distance by explaining differences in degree
and kind. In examining Confucius' understanding of ritual (li) in the
Analects, I might draw parallels with an orchestral
performance,[54] but I am
careful to explain that this is a metaphor that makes intuitive sense
but is not meant to be an illustration of the Confucian
implementation of li, which is historically and culturally
delimited.
By simply being clear about what I do and do not understand and at
what levels, misinformation is avoided, students receive a more
effective presentation, and they themselves may become more aware of
the limits and possibilities of their own discourse.[55]
Comparison and Conversation
One of the hallmarks of the liberal arts education found in the
contemporary American university is its multicultural character. Not
very often in past history have such a diverse curriculum and student
body been brought together in a single institution. As I look out
onto the audience before me, I cannot help but see that the encounter
between different cultures, traditions, and ideas is very real, not
merely notional, to use Bernard Williams' terms.[56]
As I am about to begin lecturing for my course on Eastern and Western
conceptions of the self, I realize that the authors, practices, and
ideas that we will be examining comparatively are already
intermingled in conversation as students talk to one
another.[57]
In the past, comparison frequently meant that one of two thinkers,
traditions, or texts being compared would serve as the standard by
which the other would be measured, or that some predetermined
paradigm would be used as the norm for classifying and evaluating the
elements of comparison.[58] It
seems that we are now moving towards a more complex approach wherein
the objects of comparison are used to illuminate one another, to
identify differences in similarities and similarities in
differences.[59] In a sense,
rather than comparing static entities presumed to exist unchanged in
abstraction, a more conversational approach is coming to the
fore.[60] However, if it were
merely a friendly conversation, then it would not be possible for
each to call the other into question and to engage in critical
evaluation. If it were solely a question of objective comparison, it
would be easy to overlook the fact that the person undertaking the
comparison helps to shape the nature of the inquiry and has a
normative stake in doing so.
In my teaching experiences I have found that students are more
interested and willing to engage deeper levels of knowledge when the
format of a course involves this blend of comparison and
conversation, partly because they seem to feel that no single voice
or paradigm will dominate the discussion and partly because they
begin to see their own identities as being informed by the multitude
of voices found in their world, both at the macroscopic level of an
increasingly global society and the microscopic world of their
classroom. The conversational tone invites them to see the
other-in-self and the self-in-other, and the comparative thrust
enables them to evaluate and move towards a more integrated
self-understanding.
In Conclusion
Although undergraduate education is largely restricted to the
intellectual and intuitive modalities, the teacher can articulate her
or his understanding of texts more fully and skillfully at these
levels if thought has been given to one's knowledge at the affective
and somatic levels. When appropriate, the door can then be opened to
deeper levels of engagement. Even if a student gains only a glimpse
of other possibilities, the manner in which we as teachers articulate
ourselves may very well lead students to reflect later on in life
about what it means to read, think, discuss and enlarge one's world
of knowledge in a variety of ways. I can report that students have
already taught me much and enriched my life immeasurably by
contributing to my knowledge at various levels of engagement.
Professional
Method and Personal Engagement
Louis E. Newman
When I came to Carleton [College] eleven years ago,
straight out of graduate school, I was ill-prepared for the
challenges that faced me as a teacher. Like most people in my
situation, I had never been taught how to lecture, lead discussion,
compose exams, or evaluate student work. I was very unsure about how
to play the role I had taken on, and, not surprisingly,
hypersensitive about how I appeared to my students. My main goal at
first was to become comfortable in this new persona.
Teaching successfully, it seemed to me at the time, was basically
a matter of acquiring certain specialized skills. During that first
year I got a good deal of support, both from departmental colleagues
and from Carleton's Student Observer program, whereby students sat in
on my classes and gave me their suggestions for improvement.
Experience itself proved to be an effective teacher.
Gradually, I became more comfortable in my professional role, more
competent, more relaxed about the image I presented of myself. By the
end of that year and into the next, student evaluations became more
positive. I felt proud of my progress. I had really made it; I had
become a teacher. Or so I thought.
A shift in orientation
In the years since then, I have come to look at teaching quite
differently, though I cannot now recall when my orientation first
began to shift. To be sure, professional competence counts. There are
certain skills involved in teaching which we all must learn. But
these tools no longer determine the way I measure myself as a
teacher.
I now view teaching as an interpersonal relationship, more than a
professional one. It is not fundamentally about skills and
competence, but about integrity and openness. I have begun to measure
success in terms of the quality of our interaction. All of this stems
from an awareness that, banal as it sounds, students are people. They
come to school with a whole host of baggage, most of it much heavier
and less apparent than the trunks we see them lugging across campus.
They come with loads of insecurities about who they are, who they
would like to be, and anxieties about living up to adult
expectations. And what is true of my students is equally true of me.
I believe that openly acknowledging those very personal qualities of
our lives as teachers and students is central to what I do.
When students walk through the classroom door, they do not leave
their personal lives behind; neither do we. To pretend that we do is,
at best, a form of self-deception. When students receive a poor grade
on a paper or flounder during a class presentation and come to talk
with me about it, I am faced on one level with a professional
problem: how can I help them do their best work. Maybe they need help
understanding the material, or honing their reading and writing
skills, or learning how to manage their time better. Maybe the
resources that the student used were unhelpful, or the assignment was
unclear. All of these are possibilities. Figuring out how to diagnose
such problems would be helpful were a big part of learning how to be
a teacher those first few years.
Recognizing the real task
But over time I have learned to attend to another set of concerns
entirely, and so to ask other questions. Is this student in the midst
of some personal crisis at school or at home so she can't concentrate
on her work? Is this a freshman who thinks his acceptance to Carleton
was a fluke and now is simply terrified that he can't keep pace with
his peers? Is this student so anxious to figure out what I'm looking
for, or so concerned to find the right formula for success, that her
own creative energies have been blocked? If this student is the first
person in his family to go to college, is he burdened by totally
unrealistic expectations, either of himself or of the educational
process?
Sometimes, of course, none of these personal factors is involved.
If that's the case, my interaction with that student is focused
strictly on the academic problems. More often that not, though, when
I begin to ask any of these sorts of personal questions, students
feel they have permission to talk about whatever it is that may be
affecting their work. When they do share that sort of information
with me, the teacher-student relationship is not really about
academics at all. It's about an older person helping a younger one
cope with life. The challenge to me as a teacher at that point is not
to solve their academic problems, but to empathize with their human
situation.
I can't generally help students solve their personal problems, but
now I can at least acknowledge that they exist. I can, if I choose,
even reveal the secret that I too have felt insecure, or incompetent,
or just plain stupid. Amazingly, this often comes as a great surprise
to students, but almost invariably it helps them accept their own
humaneness. And that, it now seems to me, is my real task as a
teacher.
I once assumed that my job was only to teach them about religion
or, more broadly, about how to think clearly and learn effectively. I
still think that is true, though I now understand that is but a small
part of what I should be teaching them.
An expression of values
In every interaction, I have an opportunity to teach students
something of value: how to take responsibility for themselves, how to
listen carefully, how to respond honestly, how to be sensitive to
those with special needs, how to cooperate with others even in a
competitive setting, to name only a few. It seems to me, in fact,
that the whole debate about teaching values in education is
misdirected. The fact is that all teaching is value laden, not only
because what we teach is necessarily infused with values, but more
importantly because the very act of teaching (and of living) is an
expression of values. When I succeed in communicating clearly,
grading fairly, remaining open to criticism, I am not only doing my
job well as an educator, I am teaching them something about being a
responsible person. And my suspicion is that they will remember that
lesson long after the assignments and grades have been forgotten.
J. Giles Milhaven
Does it belong to good college teaching to enable and encourage
the student to develop emotionally? Whether or not it be true of all
college courses, is it true of many -of any?- that they do, or
should, lead the student out (e-duc) not only further into knowledge,
insight, information, etc. but also further into passion, feeling,
affect, etc.? I put this question to the last three Deans of the
College at Brown, Deans Massey, Sheridan and Blumstein, during the
deanship of each of them. All three courteously and sympathetically
declined to answer, saying they did not feel competent to say
anything on the question. I respect these three educators. I respect
their declining to answer. But a fool can rush in where angels fear
to tread.
Does it belong to good college teaching to enable and lead the
student to develop emotionally? The question is, I believe, at first
answered readily in the affirmative by most of us college teachers
and administrators. Yet the more one presses the question, the more
difficult and foggy and multiple the question itself becomes. The
more engaging and demanding and expanding. More obviously tentative
and fragmentary are any answers one comes to. In this essay I report
some of my varied wandering on the tracks of this question, some
glimpses between mists that I believe I gained and now hold for the
moment as true, and some of my resultant, present searching. I report
in order to stimulate or suggest further discussion with others,
whether you follow my lead or go off in other directions.
A few years ago, an alumnus, successful businessman, wrote Brown
faculty urging that they contribute to Brown's annual fund. He wrote
of the "impact of outstanding teachers" on him when he was a student
at Brown. He summed up the impact simply: they opened him "to the
excitement of intellectual discovery." In this alumnus, when a
student, Professor Silverman "inspired a passion for intellectual
study, a passion that has never abated." Since then I have noted
other alumni summing up what they appreciated and carried away from
their Brown education. Many times the key word was something like
"passion" or "excitement" in learning.
But the alumnus permanently impassioned by Professor Silverman
does not have today a passion for intellectual discovery in the
professor's field of media studies. I recall a colleague's once
telling me that the example of her chemistry professor had moved her
to enter her career of scholar and university professor. In medieval
literature! Over the years some students have told me I was one of
those who helped stir and move them into and in their life of
intellectual search and discovery, but for most of them it was not in
my field of inquiry. It was often in a field in which I have little
interest. We teachers can inspire students into lifelong desire of
seeking and finding knowledge while influencing them little as to
what concrete knowing they seek.
Of course, the actual knowledge that we college teachers
communicate to students is valuable. Yet while alumni often praise
gratefully various things they gained at Brown, I have heard few
-any?- mention with appreciation for itself the content of their
classes, of lectures and study. Gentle probing suggests that they
have forgotten most, if not all, of the subject matter required for
exams and papers. Not just in my courses either!
In brief, many alumni, as they look back, recognize as still with
them and valuable for itself in their ongoing lives not subject
matter but modes of inquiry and discovery that in certain Brown
courses they grew in and have since made integral part of their
lives. These are modes of inquiry and discovery that are passionate
in seeking and pleasureful in finding, in coming to know. In this
short essay I focus on what motor such inquiry. What passion? What
pleasure?
I ponder this passion for and pleasure in knowing that immediately
and indispensably moves us teachers (some of us, anyway) in our
pursuit and gain of knowledge. I ponder this same passion and
pleasure we strive to infect our students with so that the passion
and pleasure move them inescapably and extensively for the rest of
their lives. As I ponder, however, further questions come to me out
of the fog. They confront my search. It seems that I must try to
answer some of them first. In this essay I first point to some of
them for the reader's own pondering. Then for the rest of the essay I
stay with one question for a while and try to map the way a bit
towards an answer. [780]
Q. 1: just as knowledge sought and gained is often a worthy end in
itself, so, too, is not the passion for this knowing, this passion
gripping and driving me and the students in our inquiry, more than
means to an end? And this kind of pleasure we gain simply in gaining
the knowing, is it not more than welcome aftereffect? Is not such
passionate, pleasureful coming to know an important, enriching end in
itself, essential, worthy goal for university education, and
manifestly worth repeating, living out, rhythmically throughout a
lifetime?
However one answer or pass over the preceding question, an equally
sweeping, basic and practical question urges. Q. 2: Can one come to
any knowing that is not merely useful for further ends but worthwhile
in itself if one lack passion for this knowing itself? I incline to
answer the question "No!" but at the moment I cannot articulate my
evidence even to myself. The question raises subquestions that must
be first taken up. I believe, for instance, that the knowings of
certain truths of history or physics or mathematics or sociology are
not only of practical use but are also worthwhile in themselves and
in themselves are worth knowing. But, if I'm right with any one of
these kinds of knowing, how can I show this convincingly? Even if
only to myself? And, if I do, then how show that such knowing arises
only out of passion and always with pleasure?
In any case, there is "knowing" that is not really knowing. The
old axiom contains truth: the content of the notes of the professor
can pass into the notes of the student without going through the mind
of either. What teacher would deny that a student with a skilled ear,
sharp logic, minimal conceptualizing and deft verbalizing might pass
a course on, let us say, ancient Athens without coming really to know
that ancient people and their lives? It is often difficult, if at all
possible, for the professor to prevent some such students even from
getting "A" for exams and papers. There is "knowing" and knowing!
We teachers know this and work against it in order to communicate
genuine knowing to our students. We do so in part by stirring and
engaging their passion for this knowing. Our goal is not that they
figure out what we want them to think and say. Our goal is that they
do the thinking on their own dynamic, in order to come to know what
they want to know. We may have some success but we may also find
evidence for Voltaire's assertion that the passion for truth, though
the strongest of all human passions, is the hardest to arouse. It may
come to seem less strange to us that the Athenians put Socrates to
death only because he would not stop asking them questions. By his
questioning he made them realize that the answers they gave
themselves verbally as to why they did this or that important
thing-go to the temple, the assembly, the gymnasium-obviously did not
hold. They did not know why they did these things and, somewhat to
their surprise, Socrates made them face the fact they did not want to
know why they did them, much less know whether their motive was a
worthwhile one.
Socrates, as indeed Aristotle, Augustine, Luther, Kant, Sartre,
Rosemary Ruether, Carter Heyward, and others, lead me to press my
search a bit for this kind of knowing which the Athenians and all the
rest of us often neglect. It is a kind of knowing for which I and
many other teachers strive, for itself and in ourselves and others. I
mean knowing of good and evil. That is: knowing what is truly,
humanly good in itself or evil in itself. (How can I "strive for" and
yet "neglect" this knowing? I'll come to that).
Even in Anglo-American universities dominated by the ideal of
disinterested scientific method many of the faculty work to bring
about explicitly or implicitly, in themselves, their colleagues and
students, more knowing of the evil of such realities as racism,
sexism, poverty, war, and of the corresponding goods that these evils
destroy or badly diminish. As corresponding goods, I think of in my
own department courses on Stoic virtue or Buddhist compassion or
early Christian compassion in Syriac-speaking lands or contemporary
feminist critique, negative and constructive, of our present
civilization.
But not all college professors who teach about, say, racism or
poverty or sexual abuse or compassion, would grant that even if only
implicitly they teach about these realities as good or evil in
themselves. Here is another question for working with and discussion:
Q. 3: When, if ever, is it appropriate in college to aim courses at
coming to know personal or social evils or goods precisely as
intrinsically evil or good?
Yet further do I narrow my focus as I move to another question.
Suppose, at least for the sake of argument, that in certain courses,
e.g. on sexism or global starvation or child abuse, we professors do
want to teach, among other things, something about the intrinsic good
and evil of some of the realities we teach about. We want our
students, as ourselves, to come to know better this or that intrinsic
good or evil. Q. 4: Can one come to any knowing of good or evil if
one lacks passion for this knowing itself? Suppose my students' study
of such realities is motivated solely by future use of this knowing,
e.g. doing well on the exam or pleasing teacher and parents or even
in using the knowledge in some further worthy way. These can be
excellent motives, but if they are their only motives, it is not
possible, I submit, that they will come to know truly better the
human good or evil they are studying.
Part of the difficulty lies in human resistance to or difficulty
in knowing good and evil. I and others fight readily for some good
and against some evil. We believe readily that certain realities are
good in themselves or evil in themselves. But are we interested in
knowing much of what is this good and evil? Really knowing more of
the evil of sexism or starvation or war? Not necessarily. In my
experience: not often.
I have come only slowly and very incompletely to recognize that
myself and others who over years have combatted doughtily and rightly
sexism reflect rarely, if at all, how little we know of its real,
live evil and the corresponding actual good: good, human, nonsexist
living together of men and women. My belief, my conviction, in regard
to sexism is strong and active. My knowledge of the very good and
evil that I here believe in is minimal. Yes, after years of reading
and listening I know a large number of facts and truths about sexism,
facts and truths useful for combating sexism. But how well do I know
the very evil of sexism? Not much.
So, too, with heterosexism. If I believe strongly in but do not
know what good homosexual living can be, I lack a knowing valuable in
itself. My relating with gay and lesbian persons, or correspondingly
(in regard to sexism), with women, is impoverished in regard to what
it could be. Moreover, my efforts to carry out actively my
convictions and bring about in our society more equality of women
with men or of homosexuals with heterosexuals may as a result be less
effective.
You, reader, may be wondering more and more what I mean here by
"know". I wonder, too. But my wondering is not mere speculation. My
wondering has grown with a growing number of convergent experiences.
I will now point to a few of them and then be silent, leaving the
reader to reflect.
Students or others I know who have suffered child abuse have
often, intentionally or unintentionally, communicated to me, who have
not so suffered but talk on the subject, how little I know the evil
of being abused as a child. I know it only a little even though I
have become informed on facts, statistics, action to be taken, etc. I
find myself talking, e.g. in ethics class, as if I know well the
evil. I don't. I may use the same words as they do but I know little
what evil was done them and to some extent still lives in them. So,
too, with those who have shared with me and my class their being
date-raped.
This question about knowing good and evil expands into countless
facets that provoke further essential abstract questions. What do we
here mean by "evil"? By "good"? By "knowing"? But right now I make
myself turn to real, individual experiences of good or evil, such as
this human being's date rape or abuse as a child. I turn to
experiences that I have not had but others share with me. As I
listen, can I learn, come to know, something of what they knew in
that experience and now know for the rest of their life? It helps me,
I find, to recognize that the knowing here by most of them is of a
similar, singular kind. It is this knowing that I want to share and
they want me to share. What kind of knowing is it? What characterize
such knowing? Passion, feeling, yes, but it is more than the simple
passion for knowing I discussed above.
I conclude this essay, not by attempting to answer these
questions, but by moving towards answering. I simply list some
relevant experiences of evil recounted in class over the years by
students or colleagues of mine. I leave the reader and myself to
ponder, perhaps try to share, something of these individuals'
knowing. And try to trace out characteristics of this knowing. Those
of us there listening were helped to share the speakers' knowing
because we heard their voice, almost always a tense, intense
monotone, as they spoke and we sensed how all of us listened intent,
gripped, unmoving.
*Yasher, Palestinian, recounts with muted anger how Israelis
evicted his family from home, livelihood and land.
*Deborah describes her attacks of deeply embodied turmoil and pain
as her mother, after years of dying, died.
*For years Angela was haunted by shame and guilt, recalling how on
a picnic she in drunken stupor was raped by her boyfriend. Only
yesterday did anger sweep up in her and she spent a half hour of
fantasy subjecting him, with whom she long had lost contact, to
various torture and humiliation. She recounted this fantasizing with
humor and, she said, definitive peace on the subject. She could move
on.
*Alan, a gay man, gave us a dramatic presentation, sad, angry,
humorous, triumphant, of what a gay man often experiences from
straight men.
*Martha, accompanied to class this time by her husband, recounted
her repeated sexual abuse in her early teens by her father.
*Thad, black chaplain, exemplified how racism is underground
nowadays, but alive and well: he notices how in an elevator white
people put space between him and them that they do not do with white
men.
How then does, for example, Thad's words increase a little my
knowing the evil of racism? Surely I have had for many years will and
passion for knowing this evil? But Thad, standing there quietly,
stirred a different passion that moved me forward, however slightly,
to know this evil more.
So, analogously, with my other examples referred to above. Could
it be that what opens me to know more is not a passion to know
anything generally? It is a different kind of passion rising unbidden
in me as this person speaks to me. Is it not a passion to share this
woman or this man's experience? To know what they know because I feel
for them? If possible, to feel what they feel? Do I not get a deep,
very bitter sweet pleasure at this knowing feeling for and with this
individual?
It is a surge of passion, of feeling, with which I may open myself
to this lived evil of the person telling me of it. Even if I thus
come to know his or her tragedy a little better, I have come also to
recognize how little I know it because I feel so much less than the
person sharing with me. Passion is not dictatable on demand. There
are human evils that I have had to recognize in talking with victims
that I know hardly at all their real evil!
Donna M. Wulff
In the present essay, I seek to convey something of the flavor of
a classroom exercise that I have found leads to a unique form of
experiential learning. I am not unaware of the irony involved in
setting out to write a scholarly piece about an experience. When
someone asked the late dancer Isadora Duncan what one of her dances
meant, she is supposed to have replied, "If I could tell you, I
wouldn't have to dance it." Accordingly, my account of what we did
and of my students' comments immediately afterward can be at best a
pale reflection of the experience itself. I offer it in the simple
hope that it may stimulate thought about other experiential
approaches to teaching.
I have long rejected the notion that religions are abstract
systems of ideas that can be adequately presented and analyzed
philosophically. In courses on the Hindu tradition, for example, I
play excerpts from tapes of Vedic chanting and talk about sound
patterns and their effects on consciousness, as these are set forth
in classical Indian treatises. In courses on the Buddhist as well as
the Hindu tradition, I show films of evocative ritual and performance
sequences and discuss the shared experiences to which they may lead,
in the light of broad social and cultural patterns, including
prevailing mythic structures.
Another major goal of my teaching is to encourage students to be
active rather than passive learners. There are many ways of
accomplishing this objective through the skillful use of such
traditional methods as lecturing, leading discussions, and assigning
papers. However, I have found students' learning enhanced by such
non-traditional techniques as setting up a class debate on a
controversial issue or designing an exercise in which students
participate actively in the process of discovery. For example, having
heard that a prominent performer of classical Indian dance would be
teaching a class of modern dance students in Brown's Ashamu Dance
Studio, I decided to take the students in my methods seminar to
witness the lesson. We had just been studying anthropological
approaches to religion; their task was to become cultural
anthropologists, observing this intercultural encounter and writing
field notes on the basis of their observations. The results of this
experiment were dramatic. Several students in the seminar had
protested, claiming that the exercise would have little or no
educational value. However, even the most skeptical among them had to
acknowledge its worth when I read them excerpts from their accounts:
these were so disparate-even at points mutually contradictory- that
it seemed as if the students had not even witnessed the same event.
Their own field notes graphically demonstrated a point that I had
been trying to make, that ethnographic accounts, which seem so solid
and definitive once they appear in print, are in fact conditioned by
any number of subjective factors.
Among the exercises that I have carried out, my favorite is one
that was inspired by a single footnote in Edward Conze's Buddhist
Thought in India. Conze suggests that the Japanese language, with its
use of impersonal constructions, lends itself far better to the
expression of Buddhist ideas than does English, with its heavy use of
personal pronouns.[62] While
one might smile today at Conze's cultural naivete, what would happen,
I wondered, if a class were to attempt to minimize or even eliminate
such pronouns? An idea for an exercise had been born.
I have used the exercise in my sections of Religious Studies 3,
"Introduction to Eastern Religions," after the class spends two weeks
reading and hearing lectures on the teachings of the Buddha, as these
have been formulated by the early Buddhist community. When I
introduce the task to the section, I don't mention pronouns. I simply
ask the class to list everything that would have to be avoided if we
were to use English in a way that does not violate the insights of
the early Buddhist teaching. Chief among these insights are that all
conditioned things, including states of consciousness, are
impermanent (anicca), that there is no unchanging eternal essence in
a human person (anatta), and that all things and states in the
conditioned world are radically interdependent (paticca-samuppada).
As students list words and phrases that imply existents that the
early Buddhists denied, such as a substantial self, I write them on
the board, and the class strives to speak without using these words
and phrases. One of the first to be mentioned is always the word "I,"
and this is usually followed by the related terms, "my," "mine," and
"me." Other personal pronouns invariably follow. There is sometimes
debate about the plurals, but it is usually acknowledged that "we"
and "they," as well as "us" and "them," likewise contain major
distortions. What, though, about the words "it" and "one"? These are
usually retained, because they are judged to be less distorting that
"I" or "you." Other terms that are sometimes debated are "love" and
"hate," but these are usually allowed so long as they are recognized
to be transitory states. Substantives as a whole have even come under
attack at times: students rightly note that nouns create the illusion
of unchanging entities. Two of my favorite substantives to be
subjected to such an analysis are "enemy" and "border," entities
whose lack of an unchanging substratum is obvious, once one thinks
about it.
The reader may well be wondering how the students can be saying
anything at this point, now that so many basic elements of the
language have been declared off limits. In fact, they do so haltingly
and imperfectly. At some point, someone usually comes up with the
idea of using impersonal constructions, and the expression "I think,"
for example, might be replaced with "It is thought" or "A thought has
occurred in this corner of the room." Similarly, "I don't like that
idea" might become "A feeling of antipathy toward that idea has
arisen in this constellation of momentary psycho-physical entities
called a person." Cumbersome, you may say. Indeed. But this very
difficulty is essential to the experience and to the learning it
promotes.
Once the class has identified elements of the English language
that are not in accord with early Buddhist teaching, and has
struggled for half an hour or so to speak without using these words
and constructions, I declare the exercise over. I then spend the last
ten minutes or so of the class doing a debriefing. The students'
comments point to aspects of their experience that I had not
anticipated before I tried the exercise with a class. The first
comment is usually about how difficult the exercise was, and how
awkward they felt at first. Everyone can relate to this comment, and
there are some relieved smiles. The students invariably go on,
however, to reflect out loud on deeper layers of the experience. They
often express surprise that an atmosphere of cooperation prevailed
throughout the exercise, replacing the competitive atmosphere that
they say is universally present in their classes at Brown. They
sometimes report that they experienced a falling away of ego, and
thus a lack of self-consciousness in being conduits for the new ideas
that came to them. They tell of having felt a strong sense of peace
and well-being in this setting, a freedom from the tensions
engendered by competition.
In addition to the absence of tension and of the usual barriers
between students, a few students report that they experienced a lack
of the hierarchy that usually characterizes the relation between
student and teacher. During the exercise they felt that we were all
on the same level. My experience accords with theirs: while we were
doing the exercise, I, too, spoke haltingly and imperfectly. For its
duration, I hardly had the sense of being any sort of authority.
Finally, students report different reactions to the pace of the
discussion. Some give voice to their frustration at not having been
able to express themselves as easily and quickly as usual. Others,
however, say they liked the slower pace, pointing out that the task
made everyone think a lot more before they spoke, and that the pace
gave listeners time to reflect on what the speaker was saying and to
ponder its relation to their own experience. Some especially
perceptive students are able to discern a meditative quality to the
discourse; I liken it to a Theravada walking meditation in which the
slowly walking monk is to say internally, "Now the Tathagata (here,
the monk) puts his left foot in front of his right foot, and now the
Tathagata puts his right foot in front of his left foot. (A far cry
from the frantic pace of life to which students of the nineties are
accustomed!)
In a short space of time, roughly half an hour, students have
experienced in nuce some of the goals of early Buddhist practice: the
falling away of ego, the sense of connectedness to all other persons
in the room, the dissolution of class hierarchy, and a certain
meditative calm. I make no claim that our classroom exercise
corresponds directly with anything that Buddhists do or ever have
done. Neither do I mean to assert that Buddhist history has been free
of classism and hierarchy. Yet this exercise has served to provide a
glimpse of the profundity and truth of the early Buddhist vision.
The experiment has not always worked perfectly. On occasion, a
resistant student has disrupted the proceedings, impatient with the
slow pace or uncomfortable with his inability to speak in accordance
with the increasing restrictions on language. The exercise is
vulnerable to such disruption by virtue of its open, democratic
structure. The student, however, can usually be prevailed upon to
give it a try, or at the very least to remain quiet for the short
time that remains so that others may participate.
I originally undertook this exercise as an experiment. The
strikingly consistent results over more than a dozen trials have
convinced me that it is worthwhile. Students often single it out for
comment in their course evaluations, citing its value for helping
them understand early Buddhist insights and experience. A unique
blend of analytical and experiential learning, the exercise will
doubtless remain in my students' memories long after all my lectures
have been forgotten.
or
How to be a Poststructuralist in the Classroom[63]
David Ross Fryer
The classroom has been historically a place for elites to teach
the canon-for a capitalist patriarchal society to further its ideas
through its own construction- authority. Multiculturalism entered the
classroom as a challenge to Western universalism and elitism. We are
now taught that the other of an other culture is not inferior but
different, and we approach these traditions with respect and
deference. U.S. second-wave feminism succeeded in adding women's
voices to a male debate, arguing that women's experience was often
different from men's, that the perspective of the person was not
something which should be shunned in favor of an objective God's-eye
"view from nowhere" in favor of arguing from where one stands.
Experience stands at the forefront of these battles. When we look at
the experiences of other cultures, of other peoples, of ourselves,
perhaps we can learn to do away with our false sense of the
universal, with our naive belief in objectivity. But is objectivity
the only thing we need to question? Is the Western white male
universal the only danger in patriarchal culture? Will any
exploration of another culture lead to a more open-eyed approach to
cultural difference? Will the act of granting authority to women
result in toppling the Phallus?[64]
How do we deal with these questions, and, consequently, how do we
deal with the problem of "experience"?
There are two kinds of experiences that enter the classroom with
which we need to deal. The first is the experience of the other as an
object of study-of particular importance in the religious studies
classroom given the confessional texts and traditions we study. The
second is the experience of the self as a source of authority-again,
of particular importance in the religious studies classroom, given
the existential nature of the subject matter we study. We begin with
the first.
In religious studies especially, experience is a problematic
category. William James's pioneering studies of religious experience
argued from the perspective that one could benefit from studying
people's experience. Recent writings in the phenomenology of religion
have sought to further James's model by placing experience in its
proper context.[65] Some of
the most recent writings on pedagogy in religious studies argue for a
decidedly experiential approach to studying religious phenomena. One
important example is found in Stephen Dunning's recent article,
"Autobiography and the Introductory Course." In it, Dunning argues
that "autobiographies confront the students immediately with the fact
that religions are made up not just of doctrines or dates, but of
individuals and groups who are struggling to find meaning in their
lives."[66] He continues,
telling us that this approach
can provide students with, so to speak, bridges from their familiar world to a new world of spiritual commitments that were previously unimaginable to them. These bridges help students to become aware of how very different alien traditions really are. They do not make understanding of the otherness of others easy, but they can help to make it possible.[67]
The problem with Dunning's approach, of course, is not its use of
the personal narrative as a means of exploring otherness; nor is it
Dunning's commitment to preserving the otherness of the other.
Rather, the problem is the exclusive use of the personal narrative in
an introductory course, which will in the long run undermine
Dunning's dual goal of connection and respect. In confining oneself
to autobiography, one furthers the belief that experience is
foundational, thus undermining the possibility for a student to
connect fully and adequately with the other. If the only texts read
are ones written "from within" it becomes difficult for the student
to get inside.[68] Moreover,
when seen within the context of an "Introduction to Religions"
course, such a syllabus may lend itself to the reification of the
belief in a pluralistic hypothesis as found in, for example, W. C.
Smith or John Hick-an approach fundamentally opposed to furthering
Dunning's dual commitment to connection and respect.[69]
The pluralist focus on commonality between various quests
undermines precisely the specificity it wishes to address, for all
differences become secondary to the primary shared goal-the human
response to mystery, infinity, what-have-you. When differences are
approached with an eye towards what they share, what they all share,
the differences become only "cultural" constructions of a deeper
underlying "reality." To critique this is not to say that there isn't
such a reality underlying these differences. Rather, it is to say
that when the arrogance of the scholar emerges such that he thinks he
can locate this reality, or at least locate its existence, regardless
of the unknowability of its traits, difference becomes simply an
issue to be understood and overcome, not its own "reality" to be
embraced and celebrated. In seeing a single thread running through
all the specific manifestations of the shared belief, false
universalism overtakes real difference and erases it.[70]
Instead of the single thread model, we need an overlapping threads
model, seeing various traditions crisscrossing each other in a
mutually engaged playing field. When we approach the other with both
wonder and interest, with the hopes of making connections,
understanding, seeing points of agreement and disagreement, without
the hidden agenda of reductionism or "commonality" (another way of
saying we are in fact really the same), then true difference can
emerge in its positivity and we can engage the other without reducing
her to the same. I would call this model one of engaged respect-one
which does not enclose the other's experience in an iron cage free
from critical-contextual evaluation, but which does allow for a
mutually engaged response to the difference of the other, one which
allows the other to be other, yet necessitates connection without
demanding sameness.[71]
It is clear how much we have learned and will continue to learn
from experiential studies of the sort Dunning advises us to read-when
couched in the proper (read non-pluralist) theoretical framework.
Studying the experiences of a particular religious group with an eye
towards internal understanding (which is not to say we are not
engaged in critical explanation as well and at other times) is an
essential component of our teaching and research. But the second
question remains: what do we do when the experience that enters the
classroom is that of a student-when the experience we are confronting
is no longer that of the other but that of the self, the
student-self, when the voice from the class speaks "But in my
experience . . . "? Is this a welcome and necessary component of the
teaching process, or a hurdle that needs to be overcome?
Questions of experience, subjectivity, and authority have found a
prominent place in recent writings on feminist and poststructuralist
theory. Charges of elitism, reverse discrimination, complicity, and
naivete fly from both sides of the debates. The battle over the place
of personal experience in theory is far from over, and while it is
easy to take sides, it is unclear where the debate is moving next.
The call to personal experience which became so powerful with the
eruption of second wave feminism was at first a response to the
feigned objectivity engendered by the positing of the male as the
universal. As objectivity and neutrality came into question, the move
to locate oneself in one's historical and cultural context, the need
to "speak from somewhere," became an essential component of the move
to undermine the oppression and domination of patriarchal thought.
However, as Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak argues, as the various
political movements of the sixties and seventies progressed in our
highly personalist culture, the battle cry "the personal is
political" soon degenerated into the belief that "only the personal
is the political."[72] The
question facing us now is, what do we do with personal experience?
The stakes are high wherever this debate takes place-perhaps nowhere
more so than in the classroom.
The voice of experience is often invoked to validate a student's
right to enter into a debate. This is one of the great achievements
of second-wave feminism. The voice of experience can be a significant
event in a student's career. Being able to add her own life to the
discussion can give the student a new found feeling of control and
importance, or competence and insight, which we as teachers need to
foster in those whose minds we touch. It can be an especially
liberating moment for a student who has trouble expressing his
opinion. And given the large number of students who have been
historically excluded from the conversations-women, people of color,
lesbian, gay, and bisexual students, for example-it is clear that the
common discourse which has been formulated over the years is lacking
in perspective and diversity. Clearly, we need to be adding the
voices of those who have been ignored or silenced. But as experience
has caught on as a "place from which to speak" it has usurped other
positions, non-experiential ones, and made them untenable. Diana Fuss
tells us, "[i]t is the unspoken law of the classroom not to
trust those who cannot cite experience as the indisputable grounds of
their knowledge."[73]
Unfortunately, such a law results in stifling as opposed to
furthering conversation. A student is often forced to begin her
statements with the words "as a . . ." or, more forcefully, "in my
experience as a . . ." A student speaking from his own experience
will not accept any challenges from other students, believing that
personal experience is itself an unshakable foundation of thought,
and that no one else can "understand my experience." Additionally,
this belief in the foundational status of experience allows a student
to forgo any argument or analysis-experience, she believes, is
enough. The once political voice of experience becomes the voice of a
particular kind of politics-a reactionary separatist unchallengeable
politics that seeks to accentuate difference at the expense of
understanding and connection.[74]
In this, as Fuss warns, that "contrary to the well-worn feminist
dictum ´the personal is the political,' personalizing
exploitation can often amount to de-politicizing it."[75]
So, we do need to continue to add voices to the conversation, to
diversify the discussion. But should adding voices to a debate also
entail delegating out new authority? When we expand the conversation,
is our goal a larger pool of conversational authority, or a different
kind of conversation? Here we must remember that not only does the
privileging of experience often invalidate other epistemological
starting points, it wrongly asserts that experience is in fact itself
a good foundation for authority. Poststructuralist theory has
fortunately taught us otherwise. Through Lacan's reading of Freud and
Derrida's readings of, well, just about everyone, we are coming to
realize that experience alone is not the key to truth, but that
experience, and truth itself, are ideological productions, occurring
in the structures of language and society and the depths of the
unconscious.[76] We don't
really know what/as we think we do. Looking back on her own career as
a feminist theorist struggling with poststructuralism, Spivak reminds
us, "may [we] not forget to question: what it is to assume
that one already knows the meaning of the words" (or the thoughts, or
the actions).[77] All our
thoughts, even those which are rooted in our personal experience, are
open to interpretation, are laden with ideology and the
unconscious-we cannot forget this.
Of course we do not want to silence students who are already
silenced by the structures of oppression they find in society.
Rather, we want to encourage them to speak, to engage, to bring their
voice, and yes even their experiences into the discussion. If, in
fear of the evils of authority and mastery, we continue to silence
those who are already silent, while we may think we are attacking the
structures which oppress, we are in fact only buttressing them from
another angle. We must be consistent in our struggles and consistent
in our attempts to empower those who have for so long been dismissed.
Fuss reminds us: "The anti-essentialist displacement of experience
must not be used as a convenient means of silencing students, no
matter how shaky experience has proven to be as a basis of
epistemology."[78]
So, given all of the rights and wrongs of the voice of experience,
how is one to go about teaching? In a recent issue of Religious
Studies News: Spotlight on Teaching, Robert Detweiler has given us
just the direction we need:
the poststructuralist notions of text, discourse, and language
might inspire us to rethink the power relationships between religion
teacher and student. These are always more complex than one thinks,
because many students of religion take it personally, and many of us,
at least secretly or unconsciously, like that. I work with many
doctoral students teaching for the first time, and their early
impressions generally include a version of the surprised comment, "My
class takes me very seriously." My response to that tends to be,
"Yes, but you shouldn't take that seriously." Why not? Well, because
you can then fall into the illusion that you have something special
to say, that you have the right, if not the duty, to manipulate your
students' lives-an impulse that to my mind is lethal. It is a
temptation that religion professors are especially vulnerable to,
since the subject matter gets so close to the existential core, and
the response, I believe, should be: resist it, and turn the
opportunity to exercise power into an analysis of power that will
profit your students and yourself.[79]
Detweiler teaches us an important lesson. For that we should all
thank him-or, perhaps, better we should ponder what it is for him to
have taught us at all. Poststructuralism teaches us that power and
authority are not problematic simply because they have been placed in
the hands of a select few-rather, they are problematic (which is not
to say evil or completely beyond redemption) in and of themselves; it
is not simply the "who" that oppresses, but the "what" of the "who,"
as well.
What's a teacher to do? For one thing, we should remember that we,
too, are students, and always will be-and that some of our best
teachers are those we set out to teach. Additionally, we must
remember that while we must strive to add many voices to a debate
previously dominated by a few, we must be careful not simply to
reduplicate the oppressive structures by placing them in the hands of
the oppressed.[80] Finally, we
must continue to remember what it is we are doing when we teach-we
are touching minds. I dare not say shaping-that would be arrogant-but
I also dare not undermine the power we do have when we teach. If we
remember what our task is-to open up new worlds and new ideas to
those who want to know-perhaps we may find some success.
Jung Lee
Without one there cannot be many and without many it is not
possible to refer to one.
-Nagarjuna, Seventy Stanzas
It is a little known fact of Wittgenstein's much heralded life
that during the early 20's, shortly after his tour of duty in the
Austrian Eleventh Army, he was employed as a primary school teacher
in a tiny village called Trattenbach. Disillusioned by the sort of
academic dilettantism that he suffered at Cambridge, Wittgenstein
entered the ranks of the teaching profession accoutered with an
idealistic set of intentions and a Tolstoyan conception of what it
would be like to work and live among the rural poor. In keeping with
his Tractarian Weltanschauung[81]
at that time, Wittgenstein labored not to advance the external
conditions of the villagers' plight, but to better them "internally,"
to impress upon his students the value of educational attainment for
its own sake. To his credit, Wittgenstein never abated in his zeal to
convey his ideal. However, it became all too apparent to the
unwitting students of Trattenbach that Wittgenstein's zeal, instead
of confining itself to encouragement and care, dilapidated into
impatience and choler. A recent biographer characterizes the
situation as follows:
With everything he taught, Wittgenstein attempted to arouse in the
children the same curiosity and questioning spirit that he himself
brought to everything in which he took interest. This naturally
worked better with some children than with others. Wittgenstein
achieved especially good results with some of the boys that he
taught, and with a select group of his favorite pupils, mainly boys,
he gave extra tuition outside school hours. To these children, he
became sort of a father figure. However, to those children who were
not gifted, or whose interest failed to be aroused by his enthusiasm,
he became not a figure of fatherly kindness, but a tyrant.[82]
Indeed, it was not uncommon for Wittgenstein to bluster into
insufferable rages or to engage in corporal punishment (e.g., hair
pulling, ear-boxing). Ultimately, Wittgenstein was forced to resign
(in what would later be called the "Haidbauer Case") when he struck a
boy on the head two or three times, causing him to collapse.
This brief sketch reveals not so much the uninteresting truth that
corporal punishment is harmful and should be avoided, but how in some
rudimentary ways, Wittgenstein's early pedagogy was informed,
ironically, by a kind of solipsism: in essence, the ideological
reality of Wittgenstein's ideal conceptions precluded any genuine
mutual interaction between the students and the teacher, to the
detriment of both parties. J. Giles Milhaven suggests that activities
such as teaching have been paradigmatic in the Western philosophical
imagination of an ideal of self-sufficiency predicated upon the
autonomous willing of the individual. He writes,
Models deeply influencing Western thinkers from the beginning were activities such as teaching, sculpting, and ruling. The teacher becomes neither more nor less wise when the pupil learns wisdom from him. The sculptor neither gains nor loses the beauty in his mind when he carves marble. The ruler becomes neither more nor less just by making his laws and decrees just. The ideal is to be as active as possible and as little passive as possible, which means being as little receptive as possible.[83]
The hapless circumstances of Wittgenstein's foray into the field
of primary education evince the extent to which self-sufficiency (as
a model of activity) may be impoverished in grounding and providing
content to the mutual understanding and growth of teachers and
students alike. Hence, it is my wish throughout the rest of this
paper to suggest ways in which the ever-present pedagogical danger of
solipsism, manifest in a variety of forms from curricular myopia to
stifling discussions, may be avoided, or at least palliated, through
the mutual affecting and interdependence of teachers and
students.
Dogen, the thirteenth-century Zen Master, suggested four practical
methods (giving, kind speech, benevolence, and
identification/cooperation) that bodhisattvas, as people committed to
the liberation of all sentient beings, could practice in order to
embody nonselfish ways of existing in the world. Just as bodhisattvas
are said to transcend transcendence (i.e., Nirvana) through
absorption in the liberation of all sentient beings, teachers can
analogously transcend their own "transcendence" (i.e., knowledge),
albeit intellectually, through their identification/cooperation with
students. Although these instructions were originally intended for a
sectarian audience, Dogen's words speak with a vitality pregnant with
suggestions for our own teaching.
The notion that concerns us most in this regard is the wisdom of
identification/cooperation. Dogen states,
Identification means nondifferentiation-to make no distinction between self and others. For example, it is like the human Tathagata who led the same life as that of us human beings. Others can be identified with self, and thereafter, self with others. With the passage of time both self and others become one. Identification is like the sea, which does not decline any water no matter what its source, all waters gathering, therefore, to form the sea.[84]
Identification, however, should not be construed as a literal
fusion of metaphysical ultimates. The water is still the water and
the ocean still the ocean. Although the relationship between teacher
and student is not a "oneness," ontologically speaking, a substratum
of equality, even in the midst of difference, undergirds the
interactions between the two. As Dainin Katagiri indicates,
... The teacher is the teacher and the student is the student. We have to see equality, but not in the realm of equality; we have to see equality in the realm of differentiation. Differentiation must be formed not in differentiation, but in equality. Then, differentiation and equality are working in identity-action.[85]
Hence, instead of an autonomous teacher, hierarchically related to
his/her students, there is an interdependence that is responsive to
the needs and concerns of all members involved. In a classroom
setting, however, this ideal is extremely difficult to realize
because of the tension that is created between the teacher as an
authority figure and the teacher as one of many interlocutors in a
conversation. If the authoritative aspect is overly accentuated, then
we have, as in the case of Wittgenstein, a pedagogical myopia that
attends to the needs of the teacher over and against the needs of the
students. However, if the relational aspects are too heavily
underscored, the teacher's effectiveness, as a scholar and critical
voice, can be jeopardized.
Practically, one way that this tension can be mitigated is to
initially, as much as possible, enter the imaginative world of the
students, seeking to understand their concerns and needs. This first
step, if nothing else, ensures that a plurality of voices will be
discerned.[86] The teacher can
then, on the pupil's terms, try to rationalize how and in what ways
his/her views could be inadequate or unintelligible even to his/her
internal methods of rationality.[87]
Thus, for example, a teacher could, engaging a pupil in his/her
conceptual framework of Marxist feminism, question whether there is
sufficient theoretical room for the analysis of race or gender, above
and beyond their roles in economic production. Of course, dissidence
will be inevitable as is the case in any multi-vocal discussion.
However, I think that the good faith effort initiated by the teacher
will in the end provide a much fuller basis for conversation and
dialogue.
Beyond the facilitation of genuine understanding, identification,
as intimated by Dogen, furnishes a way in which interlocutors can not
only enter the imaginative worlds of others, but also be transformed
by them. Thich Nhat Hanh reveals how, at the most elementary level,
transformation can supervene upon genuine understanding:
Suppose your son wakes up one morning and sees that it is already late. He decides to wake up his younger sister, to give her enough time to eat breakfast before going to school. It happens that she is grouchy and instead of saying, "Thank you for waking me up," she says, "Shut up! Leave me alone!" and kicks him. He will probably get angry, thinking, "I woke her up nicely. Why did she kick me?" He may want to go to the kitchen and tell you about it, or even kick her back. But then he remembers that during the night his sister coughed a lot, and he realizes that she must be sick. Maybe she has a cold, maybe that is why she behaved so meanly. He is not angry anymore. At that moment there is buddh [lit. to wake up, to know] in him...[88]
Granted, the explicit task of a teacher is not to fathom the
personal tribulations that may beset his/her pupils from time to
time. However, on an intellectual plane, the dynamics of
understanding and identification can secure, through the critical
referential function of others' perspectives as well as one's own, a
kind of intellectual modesty. There is activity as well as
receptivity in the willingness of the teacher to not only give but
also to receive from his/her students. Consequently, a mutuality is
engendered through the interdependence of teacher and student to
engage in and transform each others' perspectives. This cooperative
license seems, as a model, particularly apt in our increasingly
pluralistic society in which voices often unheard are becoming all
too common in the classroom. It is through this "sufficiency of
selves sufficing for themselves and each other"[89]
that a genuine mutual affecting can take place.
Indeed, to return to the figure who served to illustrate our original problem, Wittgenstein in his mature years came to be regarded by many as a masterful teacher, demanding of his students earnest engagement yet able to illustrate his points so effectively precisely because he could understand their conceptual problems and formulate his ideas knowing how they would comprehend them.[90]
[1] This essay first appeared
in A Guide to Teaching in Religious Studies (Stanford:
Department of Religious Studies, Stanford University, 1993),
13-19.
[2] If you choose to
give out your home phone number, you will want to specify the hours
when it is okay to call. I didn't do this at first, and I received
calls at all hours of the day and night.
[3] It has been my experience
that students in the sciences and engineering are much more attuned
to the benefits of collaborative learning than are students in the
humanities and social sciences. This is an area that humanists are
still reluctant to explore.
[4] An earlier version of
this essay appeared in A Guide to Teaching in Religious Studies
(Stanford: Department of Religious Studies, Stanford University,
1993), 20-23.
[5] Stephen A. Wilson, "On
the Problem of Shyness," A Guide to Teaching in Religious Studies
(Stanford: Department of Religious Studies, Stanford University,
1993), 26-30.
[6] For Mark Gonnerman's
implementation of peer review, see his "Advice for Beginnning TAs" in
this volume on page 7.
[7] These guidelines first
appeared in A Guide to Teaching in Religious Studies
(Stanford: Department of Religious Studies, Stanford University,
1993), 38-42. The sample guidelines that follow have been updated for
this volume
[8] This essay is an
adaptation of Megumi Unno, "Writing: The Bridge between Consciousness
and Unconsciousness," Foothill College, 1990.
[9] Mary Jane Schenck,
Read, Write, Revise: A Guide to Academic Writing (New York:
St. Martin's Press, 1988), pp. 2-17, cites Peter Elbow, "Freewriting
Exercises," Writing without Teachers (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1973); Donald Murray, "Why Write?" Write to
Learn (CBS College Publishing, 1984); and William Stafford, "A
Way of Writing," Field 2, Spring, 1970.
[10] Schenck, p. 3.
[11] Schenck, p. 16.
[12] This was
originally published in TA Talk, vol. 3/2 (spring 1992), a
newsletter of the Center for Teaching and Learning, Stanford
University.
[13] *Text of a talk
originally presented to Center for the Advancement of College
Teaching , Brown University, April 1991, and at Connecticut College,
New London, CT, September 1991.
[14] FTE-Faculty
Teaching Equivalent. An administrative category used at Brown
University and other similar institutions to denote one full faculty
member's slot for one full academic year. -eds.
[15] Most of what I know
about teaching has come from studying with and observing some of the
finest teachers in our profession, including Lee Yearley, P.J.
Ivanhoe, Van Harvey and Mark Unno (although I take sole
responsibility for the views represented here). It is to them that I
dedicate this essay.
[16] Jonathan Z. Smith,
"The Introductory Course: Less is Better" in Teaching the
Introductory Course in Religious Studies: A Sourcebook, ed. by
Mark Juergensmeyer (Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1991), pp. 186-7.
[17] Ibid, p.
192.
[18] There are many other
reasons to study comparative religion: 1) We are always thinking
comparatively anyway. It is not too great of an exaggeration to say
that all understanding is, to some extent, comparative. Whenever one
studies another culture, period or person, there is an implicit
comparison with one's own horizons. We need to have a critical
understanding of what occurs in that process. 2) The understanding
and appreciation of difference is particularly important in a world
(and especially a country like the United States) where different
religious, ethnic and cultural groups are living more closely and
interdependently than ever before. 3) Anyone who is going to teach at
a multicultural institution must think about these issues. Given the
student composition of the university, if these issues are not dealt
with explicitly, then they will continue to have their influence in
various hidden ways around classrooms and seminar tables. 4) We would
have no field without it. As Jonathan Smith points out, the concept
of "religion" itself is the product of the scholarly imagination. Its
foundation is comparative. For a discussion of this, see his
Imagining Religion: From Babylon to Jonestown (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1982).
[19] The plurality of forms
of human excellence can even be illustrated from within one religious
tradition (e.g. St. Francis of Assisi, Thomas Aquinas, Meister
Eckhart, Gustavo Gutiérrez). We should also show the students
that religions are not monolithic. By entering into the conversation
of a religious tradition, students can see both the diverse nature of
the tradition as well as its unifying themes and elements.
[20] For a good discussion
of the need to combine a sympathetic understanding that makes the
agents we are studying understandable with a critical capacity that
can expose the agents' errors and contradictions (in other words, a
sophisticated combination of hermeneutics and critical theory), see
Charles Taylor "Understanding and Ethnocentricity," in his
Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), pp. 116-133.
[21] The importance of this
point was shown to me by P.J. Ivanhoe in a very helpful
conversation.
[22] For a discussion of
spiritual regret as a new religious virtue, see Lee Yearley,
"Conflicts among Ideals of Human Flourishing" in Prospects for a
Common Morality, ed. by Gene Outka and John Reeder (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1993), pp. 233-253.
[23] This is not to
say that this method is the only valid way to teach religion. I
certainly recognize the importance of other approaches to the study
of religion, including historical, political, and sociological, as
well as the approach of scholars who focus on popular religion or
cultural studies, and/or who come from a post-structuralist
perspective. A good religious studies department should have scholars
coming from a variety of different angles; their mutual conversation
is necessary for the health of the field. I would argue, however,
that the approach that I am discussing in this essay is critically
important for three reasons: 1) In introductory courses, we must
facilitate a genuine engagement with the tradition, which requires a
close, sympathetic reading of its texts and a compelling presentation
of its world-views, central questions and ongoing conversations. Of
course, this is also going to involve a discussion of the tensions
and problems within the tradition, with critical perspectives coming
both from within the tradition itself and from other perspectives. We
must begin by addressing questions before we address meta-questions
(e.g. "How is a course on the Buddhist tradition to be taught? Or, as
Smith might put it, What kind of decisions go into the making of the
syllabus?"). If we start by creating a distance between students and
the tradition, they may never truly engage with it. In other words,
we should first show what the tradition has meant to those who have
lived it, and only then show what we can do with it as scholars.
While the other approaches are important, I would argue that they are
better introduced later to the student who has already gained an
appreciation for the tradition. 2) This approach is something that is
unique to the field of religious studies. While the other approaches
can be found in departments around campus (in fact, religion is
taught in some way in almost every department), only within a
religious studies department can a student acquire the vocabulary,
knowledge and skills to enable an existential encounter and insider's
perspective. Thus, in any religious studies department, this is a
necessary, though not sufficient, approach to the study of religion,
and perhaps can be seen as the department's distinctive contribution
to the university education. 3) What is at the heart of the essay is
that this approach can stimulate reflection on the most important
issues in a uniquely effective way.
[24] Smith, "Introductory
Course," p. 187.
[25] For a discussion of
this problem, and how to meet it in the classroom, see Lee Yearley,
"Bourgeois Relativism and the Comparative Study of the Self," in
Tracing Common Themes, ed. by John Carman and Steven Hopkins
(Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1991), pp. 165-178.
[26] Lionel Trilling,
Beyond Culture: Essays on Literature and Learning (New York:
Viking Press, 1965), pp. 4-5.
[27] I believe that the
failure to truly reflect on one's most important choices for the
first few decades of one's life is what lies behind many so-called
"mid-life crises"; these seem to happen not only to those who have
failed to reach their goals, but to those who have reached their most
important goals -- becoming partner, making a certain salary, sending
the kids to good schools, etc. -- and then ask, "Now what?" They
realize that all of this has failed to bring true fulfillment.
[28] I am indebted to Laura
Medin for helping me to think through this issue.
[29] For a detailed
discussion of these issues, see Mark Unno, "Levels of Pedagogy and
Individualized Instruction," A Guide to Teaching in Religious
Studies (Stanford: Department of Religious Studies, Stanford
University, 1993), 53-58.
[30] I am indebted to Greg
Kaplan for our valuable conversations on Ricoeur.
[31] I agree strongly with
Smith when he writes, "What ought not to be at controversy is the
purpose for which we labor, that long-standing and deeply felt
perception of the relationship between liberal learning and
citizenship." (in "The Introductory Course: Less is Better", p. 188;
see the discussion that follows on that page).
[32] For a discussion of
related issues, see Adolf Guggenbühl-Craig, "Quacks, Charlatans
and False Prophets," in Meeting the Shadow, ed. by Connie
Zweig and Jeremiah Abrams (Los Angeles: Jeremy P. Tarcher, 1991), pp.
110-116.
[33] This essay is offered
in honor of Lee Yearley.
[34] Søren
Kierkegaard, The Concluding Unscientific Postscript to the
Philosophical Fragments, Trans. by Howard V. Hong and Edna H.
Hong, Princeton: Princeton UP, 1992. p. 193.
[35] p. 196.
[36] p. 197.
[37] p. 198.
[38] Stephen Evans,
Kierkegaard's "Fragments" and "Postscrip,." Atlantic
Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1983. pp. 100-102.
[39] Postscript, pp.
242-3.
[40] p. 242.
[41] p. 77.
[42] p. 79.
[43] pp. 74.
[44] pp. 358-9.
[45] p. 275n.
[46] p. 243.
[47] If subjectivity is the
truth, then investigation of previously unknown possibilities can
easily become a waste of time. Climacus writes, "The person who is so
fortunate as to be dealing with multiplicity can easily be
entertaining. When he is finished with China, he can take up Persia;
when he has studied French, he can begin Italian, and then take up
astronomy, veterinary science, etc., and always be sure of being
regarded as a great fellow. But inwardness does not have the kind of
range that arouses the amazement of the sensate. For example,
inwardness in erotic love does not mean to get married seven times to
Danish girls, and then to go for the French, the Italian, etc., but
to love one and the same and yet to be continually renewed in the
same erotic love, so that it continually flowers anew in mood and
exuberance..." (pp. 259-60). Kierkegaard was no friend to the
comparative religionist of his day, but he might come to understand
why what I propose is not as pernicious as the "System."
[48] Obviously some
positions will have to be rejected as well.
[49] The degree to which
this is appropriate depends on the specific context, as I discuss
below. For the psychodynamics I describe to operate, however, this
retreat to hiddenness must occur in some form. Nevertheless, critical
judgments are made and demanded in the context of discussing and
writing papers about the various positions presented. One teaches the
intellectual virtues inherent in good criticism in the context of
more individualized instruction in section and in the evaluation of
student papers.
[50] William James, The
Varieties of Religious Experience (New York: Penguin Books,
1982), 464.
[51] Cinthia Gannett
examines how the use of journals in composition courses can
contribute to engagement at the affective level: Gender and
Journal-Diaries and Academic Discourse (Albany: State University
of New York, 1992). Although I have never used journals in teaching,
I have found that when I offer paper topics allowing for first-person
narrative, students with an affinity for the affective mode often
pursue these topics to great effect. For example, I have asked
students how they might continue a diary kept by someone had they
lived longer. One such diary I have used as a text is Pure Heart,
Enlightened Mind, by Maura Soshin O'Halloran (Boston: Tuttle,
1994).
[52] Peter Berger, The
Heretical Imperative: Contemporary Possibilities of Religious
Affirmation (Garden City, N.Y. : Anchor Press, 1980)
[53] S. Nomanul Haq in his
essay, "Some Reflections on the Pedagogical Challenges of
Introductory Courses on Islam," suggests several ways to use
scholarly sources that are internal and external to a particular
text's religious and cultural traditions.
I return to the problem of applying external perspectives in the
section entitled "Comparison and Conversation."
[54] This orchestral
metaphor was given by P.J. Ivanhoe while I was a Teaching Assistant
for his course, RS55 Introduction to Chinese Thought, Department of
Religious Studies, Stanford University, Winter 1992-93. Musical
performance itself is an important example of li, but of
course this is different from an orchestral performance given by the
Chicago Symphony.
[55] David Fryer's essay on
"The Politics of Experience and the Experience of Politics" provides
multiple perspectives on the relationship between the subject matter
of a course and the voice of personal experiences. A consideration of
the various modes of appropriating knowledge may provide a means to
further differentiate this relationship.
[56] Bernard Williams,
Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1985), 160-161.
[57] The Darker Side of
Human Existence-Conceptions of the Self, East and West,
Department of Religious Studies, Brown University, Fall
1995-96.
[58] On this point see
Sumner B. Twiss' discussion of the contrast between the postmodern
phase of religious studies in contrast to earlier phases in his
essay, "Shaping the Curriculum: The Emergence of Religious Studies."
See also Twiss, "Curricular Perspectives in Comparative Religious
Ethics-A Critical Examination of Four Paradigms," Annual of the
Society of Christian Ethics (1993).
[59] See, for example, Lee
H. Yearley, Mencius and Aquinas-Theories of Virtue and Conceptions
of Courage (Albany: State University of New York Press,
1990).
[60] Anne Klein, in her
most recent book, Meeting the Great Bliss Queen-Buddhists,
Feminists, and the Art of the Self (Boston: Beacon Press, 1995),
explicitly casts her ideas in a conversational framework.
[61] Reprinted with
permission from Liberal Education, Fall 1994. Copyright held
by the Association of American Colleges and Universities.
[62] Edward Conze,
Buddhist Thought in India (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan
Press, 1967), 102
[63] The following is a
poststructuralist psychoanalytic feminist critique of experience,
authority, and tradition, with Marxist undertones.
[64] The Phallus is the
upholder of modern Western patriarchy and its power of domination and
oppression. By positing the Phallus as the master signifier,
psychoanalysis places sexual difference, understood psychically, not
physically or merely socially, as primary. Laplanche and Pontalis on
the Phallus:
In classical antiquity, the figurative representation of the male
organ.
In psycho-analysis, the use of this term underlies the symbolic
function taken on by the penis in the intra- and inter-subjective
dialectic, the term "penis" itself tending to be reserved for the
organ thought of in its anatomical reality ...
In France, Jacques Lacan has attempted a reorientation of
psycho-analytic theory around the idea of the phallus as the
"signifier of desire." The Oedipus complex, in Lacan's reformulation
of it, consists in a dialectic whose major alternatives are to be or
not to be the phallus, and to have it or not to have ... (Jean
Laplanche and J.B. Pontalis, The Language of Psychoanalysis.
New York: Norton, 1973, pp. 312, 314)
Feminist writings on the Phallus are a bit more playful. For
instance, Jane Gallop tells another story:
Anna Freud was reaching maturity and began to show an interest in
her father's work, so Freud gave her some of his writings to read.
About a month later he asked her if she had any questions about what
she had been reading. "Just one," she replied, "what is a phallus?"
Being a man of science, Freud unbuttoned his pants and showed her.
"Oh," Anna exclaimed, thus enlightened, "it's like a penis, only
smaller!" - A Joke. (Jane Gallop, Thinking Through the Body.
New York: Columbia University Press, 1988, p. 124.)
In Lacanian discourse, the status of the phallus, of course, is
that of a fraud. No one can be or have the master signifier, and
while men still believe in this impossibility, women, already
excluded from the fraudulent order, don't.
[65] For a helpful
treatment of the various approaches to/in the phenomenology of
religion, see Sumner B. Twiss and Walter Conser, Experience of the
Sacred: Readings in the Phenomenology of Religion. Hanover: Brown
University Press, 1992.
[66] Stephen Dunning,
"Autobiography and the Introductory Course," in Religious Studies
News: Spotlight on Teaching, February 1995, p. 4)
[67] Ibid.
[68] I will return to this
difficulty in greater detail below when discussing the problem of a
student's personal experience as authoritative in the classroom.
[69] It is not my intention
to suggest that Dunning himself believes in the pluralist hypothesis
- his own work radically suggests otherwise. My point is, instead,
that his choice of autobiography as the sole text for study in the
introductory course betrays his best intentions, and places his
commitment to connection and respect in jeopardy.
[70] None of this is, of
course, the goal of either Smith's or Hick's approaches. My argument
here is that it is the necessary and unfortunate consequence of such
approaches.
[71] This is precisely the
approach which Irigaray advises we take on the question of sexual
difference. See Luce Irigaray, An Ethics of Sexual Difference.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1985. I believe it is also similar
to what Ellen Rooney works toward in her brilliant critique of
pluralism. See her Seductive Reasoning. Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1989.
[72] Gayatri Chakravorty
Spivak with Ellen Rooney, "In a Word. Interview," in Naomi
Schor and Elizabeth Weed, The Essential Difference.
Providence: Brown University Press, 1994, p. 155.
[73] Diana Fuss,
Essentially Speaking. New York: Routledge, 1989, p. 116.
[74] Again, note that I
cite the problem of accentuating difference at the expense of
understanding, not at the expense of commonality. The point of this
essay is not to argue that we must return to the essentializing
gesture of the common, but that we must seek to make connections
between and across differences - a necessary strategy often
sacrificed in the name of the personal.
[75] Fuss, p. 117.
[76] A few brief words are
perhaps in order about poststructuralist theory. It is nearly
impossible to sum up poststructuralist thought as it informs this
paper in a few brief sentences, I will make no pretensions to doing
so. However, I will offer a brief sketch of the major commitments
underlying this paper. My own brand of poststructuralism comes very
much out of Lacanian psychoanalysis and various feminist responses to
it. My own ideological preoccupations are with the prevalence of the
unconscious, the unknowability of the known, and the impossibility of
self-mastery, and, at the same time, the necessity of identity, the
usefulness of myth, and the power of the political. These things
taken together form a radical potential for social change and
political reordering. For those of you wanting to know more about
poststructuralist theory, I highly recommend part two of Toril Moi's
Sexual/Textual Politics. London: Routledge, 1988, as an
introductory text to poststructuralism from a feminist perspective.
Robert Detweiler's "Poststructuralism and the Teaching of Religion"
in Religious Studies News: Spotlight on Teaching, May 1995, is
another excellent, much more concise, summary piece.
[77] Gayatri Chakravorty
Spivak, "French Feminism Revisited" in Judith Butler and Joan W.
Scott, Feminists Theorize the Political. New York: Routledge,
1992, p. 57.
[78] Fuss, p. 117.
[79] Detweiler, op.
cit., p. 2.
[80] James concludes that
the mystical experience is authoritative only for the one who has
that experience. While we wouldn't want to do away with all of the
authority that or any experience holds for anyone, we might want to
take experience out of its iron cage and open it up to the realities
of the psychical/social - ideology, language, power, and the
unconscious.
[81] I am referring here to
the thread of idealism that recurs throughout the Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus, trans. C.K. Ogden (New York: Routledge,
1992), especially in propositions 5.6-5.64. For example,
5.62: That the world is my world, shows itself in the fact
that the limits of the language (the language which I
understand) mean the limits of my world.
5.63: I am my world. (The microcosm.)
5.632: The subject does not belong to the world but it is a limit
of the world.
[82] Ray Monk, Ludwig
Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (New York: Penguin Books, 1990),
p. 195.
[83] J. Giles Milhaven,
Hadewijch and Her Sisters (Albany: SUNY Press, 1993), p.
42.
[84] Zen Master Dogen:
An Introduction with Selected Writings, trans. Yuho Yokoi (New
York: Weatherhill, 1976), p. 62.
[85] Dainin Katagiri,
Returning to Silence: Zen Practice in Daily Life (Boston:
Shambhala, 1988), p. 172.
[86] I am tacitly endorsing
a Gadamerian view of the cultural/linguistic embeddedness of all
understanding. Consequently, an absolute, objective standpoint,
capable of adjudicating all disagreements, is superseded by a
dialogical encounter between conditioned perspectives (i.e., a
"fusion of horizons") that not only constrains but enables the
pursuit of truth.
[87] This idea is an
extrapolation of MacIntyre's method of adjudicating between two rival
moral traditions, where one tradition, A, is rationally superior to
another, B, if A can resolve problems and anomalies in B in such a
way that B can understand why it cannot solve those problems and
anomalies utilizing the intellectual resources available to it in its
tradition. See his Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre
Dame: Notre Dame Press, 1988) and Three Rival Versions of Moral
Enquiry (Notre Dame: Notre Dame Press, 1990).
[88]Thich Nhat Hanh,
Being Peace (Berkeley: Parallax Press, 1987), p. 14.
[89] Milhaven, p. 45.
[90] To some, however, it was all too apparent that Wittgenstein never became entirely free of the overbearing attitude first manifest in his youth. Dogen, too, has at times been seen as more than a bit cantankerous in his criticisms of his contemporaries. Here it is hoped that we are inspired by the best to be found in the lives and thoughts of these figures.